Crimes Against Humanity.
May, Larry
Crimes Against Humanity: A Normative Account is the first of a
multi-volume work on the moral foundations of international criminal
law. (1) Crimes against humanity raise especially difficult questions in
international law, since they are crimes that can be committed
completely within one state's borders by members of that state
against other members of that same state. The very idea of a crime
against humanity challenges the traditional understanding of a
state's exclusive prerogative over crimes committed within its
borders. I defend a limited scope to international trials for crimes
against humanity, arguing that some crimes are so egregious that they
harm humanity and thus warrant international prosecutions.
The book is divided into four parts. The first part sets out a
theory of sovereignty, and explains why state sovereignty is not
absolute, even on a Hobbesian view, and why some norms cross borders.
The second part defends two normative principles, the security and the
international harm principles, that together justify international
criminal trials for crimes that do not themselves cross borders. The
third part defends the idea that crimes against humanity involve an
intent to participate in a widespread and systematic attack on a
population, making it very difficult, although not impossible, for minor
players to be successfully prosecuted for crimes against humanity. The
fourth part explains why prosecutions for crimes against humanity should
be limited in scope, why victims are not owed international
prosecutions, and why alternatives such as truth and reconciliation
commissions may be acceptable alternatives to international criminal
trials. Throughout, I take a moral minimalist and defendant-oriented
approach to understanding crimes against humanity.
The book begins by adopting a Hobbesian standpoint, the very
standpoint often adopted by realists who claim that there are no moral
restraints on a state's sovereign prerogative, especially in
criminal law. I argue that a Hobbesian must realize, as Hobbes himself
did, that when a sovereign either cannot or will not protect its
subjects from serious harm, then the sovereign loses exclusive
jurisdiction over such criminal matters, since for Hobbes there are
"some rights that no man can be understood ... to have abandoned or
transferred." (2) A Hobbesian minimalist can accept certain
international prosecutions, since sovereignty is not absolute. Some
norms cross borders, as it were. The most important is the norm that
people's basic security and subsistence rights should be protected
from assault, whether at the hands of individuals or governments. The
universal norms in question, sometimes called jus cogens norms, can be
supported either from a minimal natural law or a limited positivist position. But such norms are not easily grounded in mere custom or
consent. Customary norms cannot ground universal moral prescriptions,
such as those against apartheid, slavery, and genocide. But custom can
give us good evidence of what are those jus cogens norms. A Hobbesian
recognizes that some rights are universal in that they are grounded in
the natural need for security that each of us seeks, and that such
rights limit state sovereignty.
The normative core of the book is my defense of the security and
international harm principles that together ground limited international
criminal trials. The security principle expands on my Hobbesian
understanding of the limits of state sovereignty. The state can lose its
exclusive right to determine what happens within its borders when that
state participates in or allows certain human rights abuses--namely, the
deprivation of security or subsistence rights of its members. Depriving
a state of its right to exclusive jurisdiction over its own members,
however, does not yet establish that an international body can cross
that state's borders to arrest or remove its members for
international prosecution. It must also be shown that there is some
international interest in this matter that warrants interference in the
internal affairs of the state by the international community. I argue
that such an interest is best understood in terms of the international
harm principle--that is, when there is some sense in which humanity or
the international community has been harmed. International prosecutions
for crimes against humanity should only occur if there have been
widespread or systematic attacks on a population. I parse this idea to
mean that either the victim is singled out for group-based harm or that
the perpetrator is group-based in that it is associated with the state,
and optimally when both of these group-based considerations are extant.
The security principle breaks the exclusive jurisdiction of the state,
whereas the international harm principle indicates why specifically
international prosecutions can legitimately take place for crimes
against humanity.
If one can get over the sovereignty hurdle, the next question is
who it is that should be prosecuted for crimes against humanity. Here
there is a serious conceptual problem. For crimes against humanity are
mass atrocities, but it is individual persons, not states, who will be
prosecuted in international trials. I argue that normally it is state
leaders, rather than small fish, who should be in the dock, if anyone
should. I examine three trials: Dusko Tadic, the first person tried by
the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia; Adolf
Eichmann, tried in Jerusalem for Nazi atrocities; and Augusto Pinochet,
tried preliminarily in the U.K. for crimes against the Chilean people. I
use an examination of each trial to discuss what should be the actus
reus and mens tea components of crimes against humanity. I argue that in
most cases the prosecution should have to prove that the defendant had a
discriminatory intent--that is, the intent to assault a person because
of that person's group membership--as a way of linking the
defendant's state of mind and the atrocity that he or she is being
prosecuted for. International prosecutions are justifiable, but in a
more limited way than has been recognized so far, and this is true when,
and especially when, there is widespread complicity in crimes against
humanity.
There is also a good normative question about what defenses and
procedures should be used in such trials. The superior orders defense is
generally disallowed in international proceedings today, but duress has
grown in importance and can be used by many small fry, and perhaps also
by some state leaders, in international trials. In addition, there are
procedural restraints that should govern such trials, most especially
the prohibitions on retroactive prosecutions, selective prosecutions,
and disproportionate punishments. I argue strongly for an international
rule of law as a basic prerequisite for legitimate international
prosecutions. It is not sufficient that victims have had horrible things
done to them and that the world wishes to express its moral outrage.
Victims are not owed convictions; rather, it is the international
community that is the proper aggrieved party in crimes against humanity.
Finally, I ask whether it might be reasonable to hold truth and
reconciliation commissions rather than international criminal trials as
a response to mass atrocities. It is often the case that criminal trials
further enflame ethnic or religious animus among population groups in a
society. There is thus at least an initial impetus to think of less
contentious ways for civil turmoil to be brought to an end. Indeed, the
idea of apology or forgiveness is so foreign to criminal trials that one
might wonder why we should have criminal trials at all in such
circumstances. In the last chapter, I set out the arguments on both
sides of this complicated issue. I argue that in some cases it may be
justifiable not to have trials, but only in those cases where amnesty or
reconciliation programs call for some kind of serious acknowledgment of
wrongdoing along with some kind of remorse on the part of the
perpetrators of atrocities. We must be careful not to let the goals of
reconciliation swamp considerations of justice.
We stand at a crossroads in the movement for international law and
justice. I see myself as squarely in the middle of the debate about
which direction to take. On one side are those who argue for
cosmopolitan justice; and on the other side are those who urge that we
retreat from any kind of international interference in the affairs of
sovereign states. In this book, I defend a limited scope for
international trials. One of the most important limitations is that we
respect the international rule of law and not merely prosecute on the
basis of our heartfelt moral outrage in the face of mass atrocities.
Some will undoubtedly wish for a wider scope for international criminal
law than that which I defend here; still others will think that I have
gone too far. Human rights are indeed important and need to be
protected, especially when it is a state that seeks to abridge these
rights. But it is not as clear as it might seem that individuals should
be held legally accountable in international proceedings for each and
every human rights abuse. If we limit our scope, we will have a better
chance of defending trials for the most egregious of human rights
abuses.
(1) Larry May, Crimes Against Humanity: A Normative Account
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).
(2) Thomas Hobbes, "Leviathan," in William Molesworth,
ed., The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, vol. III (Aalen, Germany:
Scientia Verlag, 1966), p. 120.