Do sunk costs matter?
McAfee, R. Preston ; Mialon, Hugo M. ; Mialon, Sue H. 等
"Let Bygones Be Bygones."
--Khieu Samphan, former head of state of the Khmer Rouge government, asking Cambodians to forget the more than one million people
who died under his government's rule.
I. INTRODUCTION
Sunk costs are costs that have already been incurred and cannot be
recovered. Sunk costs do not change regardless of which action is
presently chosen. Therefore, an individual should ignore sunk costs to
make a rational choice. Introductory textbooks in economics present this
as a basic principle of rational decision making (Frank and Bernanke
2006, 10; Mankiw 2004, 297).
Nonetheless, people are apparently often influenced by sunk costs
in their decision making. Once individuals have made a large sunk
investment, they have a tendency to invest more in an attempt to prevent
their previous investment from being wasted. The greater the size of
their sunk investment, the more they tend to invest further, even when
the return on additional investment does not seem worthwhile. For
example, some people remain in failing relationships because they
"have already invested too much to leave." Others buy
expensive gym memberships to commit themselves to exercising. Still
others are swayed by arguments that a war must continue because lives
will have been sacrificed in vain unless victory is achieved.
These types of behavior do not seem to accord with rational choice
theory and are often classified as behavioral errors. People who commit
them are said to be engaging in the "sunk cost fallacy."
Students are repeatedly taught in economic classes that sunk costs are
irrelevant to decision making so that they may ultimately learn to make
better decisions, invoking the theory as a normative prescription.
Conditioning on the level of sunk costs is also taken as evidence that
people do not always make rational choices (Thaler 1991), suggesting
that the explanatory power of rational choice theory is limited.
In this article, we argue that in a broad range of environments,
reacting to sunk costs is actually rational. Agents may rationally react
to sunk costs because of informational content, reputational concerns,
or financial and time constraints.
A. Informational Content
Consider a project that may take an unknown expenditure to
complete. The failure to complete the project with a given amount of
investment is informative about the expected amount needed to complete
it. Therefore, the expected additional investment required for fruition will be correlated with the sunk investment. Moreover, in a world of
random returns, the realization of a return is informative about the
expected value of continuing a project. A large loss, which leads to a
rational inference of a high variance, will often lead to a higher
option value because option values tend to rise with variance.
Consequently, the informativeness of sunk investments is amplified by
consideration of the option value.
B. Reputational Concerns
In team relationships, each participant's willingness to
invest depends on the investments of others. In such circumstances, a
commitment to finishing projects even when they appear ex post
unprofitable is valuable because such a commitment induces more
efficient ex ante investment. Thus, a reputation for "throwing good
money after bad"--the classic sunk cost fallacy--can solve a
coordination problem. In contrast to the desire for commitment, people
might rationally want to conceal bad choices to appear more talented,
which may lead them to make further investments, hoping to conceal their
investments gone bad.
C. Financial and Time Constraints
Given financial constraints, larger past expenditures leave less
ability to make future expenditures, ceteris paribus. Thus, financial
constraints may lead companies or individuals to stick with projects
that no longer appear to be the best choice. Moreover, given limited
time to invest in projects, as the time remaining shrinks, individuals
have less time over which to amortize their costs of experimenting with
new projects and therefore may be rationally less likely to abandon
current projects.
Once all the elements of the decision-making environment are
correctly specified, conditioning on sunk costs can often be understood
as rational behavior. This has two potentially important implications.
First, the sunk cost fallacy is not necessarily evidence that people do
not make rational choices. Second, in certain situations, ignoring sunk
costs may not be rational, so people should not necessarily or
systematically ignore them or be taught to do so.
The possibility of rational explanations for sunk cost effects has
been raised before. Friedman et al. (2007) list option values and
reputational concerns as possible reasons why people might react to sunk
costs. However, they do not provide detailed explanations or models.
Kanodia, Bushman, and Dickhaut (1989), Prendergast and Stole (1996), and
Camerer and Weber (1999) develop principal-agent models in which
rational agents invest more if they have invested more in the past to
protect their reputation for ability. We elucidate the general features
of these models below and argue that concerns about reputation for
ability are especially powerful in explaining apparent reactions to sunk
costs by politicians. Carmichael and MacLeod (2003) develop a model in
which agents initially make investments independently and are later
matched in pairs, their match produces a surplus and they bargain over
it based on cultural norms of fair division. A fair division rule in
which each agent's surplus share is increasing in their sunk
investment and decreasing in the other's sunk investment is shown
to be evolutionarily stable.
Although several articles have raised the possibility of rational
and evolutionary reasons, and several have modeled one reason, for
attending to sunk costs, our article appears to be the first to
systematically model the main rational reasons for doing so. Before
presenting our formal arguments about the rationality of reacting to
sunk costs in different decision-making environments, we now review the
empirical evidence on the tendency to react to sunk costs.
II. EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE
The greater the sunk investment that individuals have already made
the more likely they are to invest further. Several studies provide
empirical evidence of this tendency. In studies by Staw (1976, 1981),
Arkes and Blumer (1985), Whyte (1993), and Khan, Salter, and Sharp
(2000), subjects were presented with various vignettes describing a
business investment project. One group of subjects was told that a large
amount had already been invested, while another group was told that a
small amount had already been invested. In almost all the cases, the
subjects with the large sunk investment chose to invest more.
Individuals who have made a large sunk investment may also have a
tendency to invest further even when the return does not seem
worthwhile. According to evidence reported by De Bondt and Makhija
(1988), managers of many utility companies in the United States have
been overly reluctant to terminate economically unviable nuclear plant
projects. In the 1960s, the nuclear power industry promised "energy
too cheap to meter." But nuclear power later proved unsafe and
uneconomical. As the U.S. nuclear power program was failing in the 1970s
and 1980s, Public Service Commissions around the nation ordered prudency
reviews. From these reviews, De Bondt and Makhija find evidence that the
Commissions denied many utility companies even partial recovery of
nuclear construction costs on the grounds that they had been mismanaging
the nuclear construction projects in ways consistent with throwing good
money after bad.
There is also evidence of government representatives failing to
ignore sunk costs. The governments of France and Britain continued to
invest in the Concorde--a supersonic aircraft no longer in
production--long after it became clear that the project would generate
little return because they had "Too much invested to quit"
(Teger 1980, title of the book).
An argument often made to stay the course in a war is that too many
lives have already been lost and that these lives will have been lost in
vain if the war is not won. In a speech on August 22, 2005, U.S.
President George Bush made this argument for staying the course in Iraq.
Referring to the almost 2,000 Americans who had already died in the war,
he said "We owe them something.... We will finish the task that
they gave their lives for" (Schwartz 2005, 1). Similar arguments
were made during the Vietnam War. As casualties mounted in Vietnam in
the 1960s, it became more and more difficult to withdraw because war
supporters insisted that withdrawal would mean that too many American
soldiers would have died in vain.
Many of the examples usually employed to demonstrate the sunk cost
fallacy consist of disasters resulting from not ignoring sunk costs. The
nuclear power program resulted in billions of dollars wasted and
expensive energy, and the Vietnam War resulted in tens of thousands of
American deaths and merely postponed the time until South Vietnam fell.
The choice of examples may in part reflect a bias on the part of
economists and psychologists trying to teach people a lesson about
ignoring sunk costs. A potentially very effective way to teach people to
ignore sunk costs is through examples in which people did not ignore
sunk costs much to society's, or their own, ultimate detriment.
But there are also examples of people who succeeded by not ignoring
sunk costs. The same "we-owe-it-to-our-fallen-countrymen"
logic that led Americans to stay the course in Vietnam also helped the
war effort in World War II. More generally, many success stories involve
people who at some time suffered great setbacks, but persevered when
short-term odds were not in their favor because they "had already
come too far to give up now." Columbus did not give up when the
shores of India did not appear after weeks at sea, and many on his crew
were urging him to turn home (see Olson 1967, for Columbus'
journal). Jeff Bezos, founder of Amazon.com, did not give up when
Amazon's loss totaled $1.4 billion in 2001, and many on Wall Street
were speculating that the company would go broke (Mendelson and Meza
2001).
Anecdotal evidence suggests that individuals may even exploit their
own reactions to sunk expenditures to their advantage. Steele (1996,
610) and Walton (2002, 479) recount stories of individuals who buy
exercise machines or gym memberships that cost in the thousands of
dollars, even though they are reluctant to spend this much money,
reasoning that if they do, it will make them exercise, which is good for
their health. A reaction to sunk costs that assists in commitment is
often helpful.
People react to sunk costs not only in investment decisions but
also in consumption decisions. In consumption, people may attempt to
redeem sunk monetary expenditures by increasing nonmonetary expenditures
of resources such as time and effort. In a field experiment with season
tickets to the Ohio University's Theater in 1982, Arkes and Blumer
(1985) found that people who were charged the regular price of $15
(about $30 in 2006 dollars) at the ticket counter attended 0.83 more
plays on average, out of the first five plays of the season, than those
who received an unexpected discount of $7 ($14 today). Staw and Hoang
(1995) and Camerer and Weber (1999) show that National Basketball
Association teams initially tend to give their early-round draft picks
more playing time than their performance justifies, perhaps in an
attempt to justify their high salaries.
People may invest more money or time if their sunk costs are
greater ("escalation of commitment"), but they may also invest
less if their sunk costs are greater ("deescalation"). While
the reported evidence typically points to escalation, Garland, Sandefur,
and Rogers (1990) provide evidence of deescalation in oil exploration
experiments. The authors gave petroleum geologists various scenarios in
which more or fewer wells had already been drilled and found to be dry.
The geologists were less likely to authorize funds to continue
exploration and their estimates of the likelihood of finding oil in the
next well were lower when the number of wells already found to be dry
was greater. Similarly, Heath (1995) provides evidence of deescalation
in several experiments with investment vignettes. He attributes the
observed "reverse sunk cost effect" to "mental
budgeting." According to his theory, people set a mental limit for
their expenditures, and when their expenditures exceed the limit, they
quit investing. People who have already invested a lot are more likely
to have reached the limit of their mental budget and therefore are more
likely to quit. We argue later that actual budget constraints can
explain not only deescalation but also escalation of commitment in
certain investment situations.
Empirical and anecdotal evidence suggests that people are often
influenced by sunk costs in their decision making. We now argue that
this is not necessarily inconsistent with rational decision making or
optimizing behavior.
III. INFORMATIONAL CONTENT
Agents may rationally react to sunk costs because such costs reveal
valuable information, both about the likelihood of future success and
about the option value of continuing to invest.
A. Changing Hazards
Past investments in a given course of action often provide evidence
about whether the course of action is likely to succeed or fail in the
future. Other things equal, a greater investment usually implies that
success is closer at hand.
Consider the following simple model. A firm has an investment
project that requires a total cost [bar.C] to complete and yields a
payoff V upon completion. The total cost [bar.C] is uncertain and is
distributed according to a cumulative distribution function G([bar.C]),
where G(x) > G(y) for x > y > 0. Suppose the firm has already
invested an amount [C.sub.1] in Period 1 and the project is not
complete. In Period 2, the firm chooses whether or not to invest an
additional amount [C.sub.2]. For simplicity, suppose the firm cannot
invest after Period 2. Denote by [p.sub.2] the probability that the
project is completed after the firm invests in Period 2.
Using Bayes' Law, we find that
[p.sub.2] = [p.sub.2]([C.sub.1], [C.sub.2]) = G([C.sub.1] +
[C.sub.2]) - G([C.sub.1])/ 1 - G([C.sub.1]).
This is the cumulative hazard of investment and it depends on the
amount [C.sub.1] already invested. The firm therefore rationally takes
into account the size of its sunk investment when deciding whether to
invest further.
Differentiating [p.sub.2]([C.sub.1], [C.sub.2]) with respect to
[C.sub.1], we obtain
[[partial derivative][p.sub.2]/[[partial derivative][C.sub.1] = 1 -
G([C.sub.1] + [C.sub.2])/1 - G([C.sub.1]) x (g([C.sub.1] + [C.sub.2])/1
- G([C.sub.1] + [C.sub.2]) - g([C.sub.1])/1 - G([C.sub.1]).
Thus, [p.sub.2]([C.sub.1], [C.sub.2]) is increasing in [C.sub.1] if
the hazard rate g(x)/1 - G(x) is increasing. That is, conditional on not
succeeding, the probability of success with a small additional
investment grows, and conversely, [p.sub.2]([C.sub.1], [C.sub.2]) is
decreasing in [C.sub.1] if the hazard rate is decreasing.
The firm's expected utility of investing in Period 2 is
[p.sub.2]([C.sub.1], [C.sub.2])V - [C.sub.2] - [C.sub.1] and its
expected utility from not investing in Period 2 is - [C.sub.1].
Therefore, the net gain from investment in Period 2 is
[p.sub.2]([C.sub.1], [C.sub.2])V - [C.sub.2] - [C.sub.1].
Suppose the hazard rate is increasing, so [p.sub.2]([C.sub.1],
[C.sub.2]) is increasing in [C.sub.1]. In this case, the willingness to
invest is rationally an increasing function of the past investment.
Similarly, the willingness to invest is rationally a decreasing function
of the past investment if the hazard rate is decreasing. The only case
in which the size of the sunk investment cannot affect the firm's
rational decision about whether to continue investing is the rather
special case in which the hazard is exactly constant.
The model suggests that in many environments, the level of sunk
costs matters to the rational inference about the likely needed future
expenditures and in such environments, sunk costs matter. The theory
admits that the effect of sunk costs on the willingness to make
continued investments is ambiguous, hinging on the derivative of the
hazard rate.
If the amount required for the project to be completed cannot
exceed some known finite amount, that is, the support of the
distribution of [bar.C] has an upper bound, then the project's
hazard rate is necessarily increasing close to this upper bound. Even
when the upper bound is not known with certainty, the hazard might be
increasing. In many investment projects, progress toward the goal is
observable or measurable. Sunk investments that have been insufficient
to achieve success then convey information about the likelihood of
future success. Consider an aircraft company engaged in a project to
develop "a radar scrambling device that would render a plane
undetectable by conventional radar" (Arkes and Blumer 1985).
Suppose the firm has spent $100 million to develop the radar-blind
plane, and while it has not achieved its goal yet, the project is now
90% complete in that, according to test results that incorporate many
variations in speed, altitude, and the level of electromagnetic
emissions, the plane is detectable only about 10% of the time, which is
slightly above the marketable level of 5%. The firm must decide whether
to invest another $100 million. While this might still be insufficient
to complete the project, the firm might expect a high probability of
completion with the additional investment based on the substantial
progress achieved through the first $100 million invested.
Learning by doing generally reinforces the conclusion that greater
expenditures should increase the willingness to continue. In the model
described above, if the firm has invested more in Period 1, it may have
acquired more knowledge and skill that will make it more likely to
succeed with the additional investment in Period 2. That is, the
probability that the firm will succeed in Period 2 may also be a
function of the firm's ability in Period 2, [a.sub.2], which may be
a function of [C.sub.1]. A greater investment in Period 1 may increase
ability, so [da.sub.2]/d[C.sub.1] > 0, which makes it more likely
that [dp.sub.2]/d[C.sub.1] > 0.
While some projects have an increasing hazard, others appear to
have a decreasing hazard. For example, curing cancer, originally
expected to cost $1 billion (Epstein 1998), probably has a decreasing
hazard; given initial failure, the odds of immediate success recede and
the likely expenditures required to complete grow. Oil exploration
projects might also be characterized by decreasing hazards. Suppose a
firm acquires a license to drill a number of wells in a fixed area. It
decides to drill a well on a particular spot in the area. Suppose the
well turns out to be dry. The costs of drilling the well are then sunk.
But the dry well might indicate that the likelihood of striking oil on
another spot in the area is low since the geophysical characteristics of
surface rocks and terrain for the next spot are more or less the same as
the ones for the previous spot that turned out to be dry. Thus, the firm
might be rationally less likely to drill another well. In general, firms
might be less willing to drill another well the more wells they had
already found to be dry. This may in part explain the rapid deescalation
observed by Garland, Sandefur, and Rogers (1990) in their oil
exploration experiments.
B. Option Values
Experience generally reveals information about likely future
values. In a world of uncertainty, maintaining an investment generates
information, while terminating often does not. Therefore, there may be
an option value to maintaining investments (Dixit 1992; Dixit and
Pindyck 1994; Pindyck 1991).
A firm may start a project because the project has a positive net
present value (NPV) and then experience a bad outcome that turns the NPV
negative; but it might nonetheless be rational for the firm to continue
investing in the project after the bad outcome because of the
"deferral" option value of maintaining the investment.
Consider the following simple three-period example. In Period 1, the
firm chooses whether or not to invest $2 in a project. If it chooses to
invest then with 1/2 probability, the project is completed and yields
$6, and with 1/2 probability, the project is not completed. If the
project is not completed then in Period 2, the firm chooses whether or
not to invest another $2. lf it chooses to invest then with 1/2
probability, the project is now completed and yields $6, and with 1/2
probability, the project is still not completed and the firm learns that
an additional $10 is required for completion. If the firm ever chooses
not to invest before completion, it receives zero.
Normalizing the discount factor to 1, in Period 1, the NPV of the
project absent the abandonment option is -2 + 0.5(6) + 0.5[-2 + 0.5(6) +
0.5(-10 + 6)] = 0.5, and in Period 2, after the bad outcome in Period 1,
the NPV of the project is -2 + 0.5(6) + 0.5(-10 + 6) = -1. However, in
Period 2, the true value of continuing the project after the bad outcome
in Period 1, which includes the value of the deferral option, is -2 +
0.5(5) + 0.5(0) =0.5 since the firm can stop investing in Period 3 if it
learns that an additional $10 is required for completion. Thus, even in
the bad state after the first round, which makes the project's NPV
turn negative, it is rational for the firm to continue investing because
of the deferral option value of maintaining the investment.
In investment projects where option considerations are important,
larger losses themselves might even be "good news" about the
value of further investment. This is an extreme form of our argument
that it might be rational to "throw good money after bad." We
illustrate the logic in a simple way. Suppose that an investment project
is one of two kinds, either with low risk and negative profit or with
high risk and positive profit. For simplicity, suppose the low-risk
project has a normally distributed return with mean [mu]L and variance
[s.sup.2], while the high-risk project return is also normally
distributed with mean [mu]L and variance [[sigma].sup.2]. Assume
[s.sup.2] < [[sigma].sup.2] and [mu]L < 0 < [mu]H, so that the
goal of the investor is to terminate the low-risk project and continue
with the high-risk project.
Given an observed return x and a prior on the high return of p, the
Bayesian update that the project has a positive return is
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
This probability is increasing in x if [(x - [[mu].sub.H]).sup.2]
(x - [[mu].sub.L]).sup.2]/2[s.sup.2] is decreasing. As [s.sup.2] <
[[sigma].sup.2], the Bayesian update is increasing if x >
[[sigma].sup.2][[mu].sub.L] - [s.sup.2][[mu].sup.H]/[[sigma].sup.2] -
[s.sup.2]. For x below [[sigma].sup.2][[mu].sub.L] -
[s.sup.2][[mu].sub.H], a lower return is good news about the prospects
for investment; the expected payoff from future investment increases as
the return decreases. In this case, the lower return signals an increase
in variance, which is good news about the value of further
experimentation. For any fixed cost of sampling, the stopping rule involves a low Bayesian update and this occurs on an interval with a
very high or a very low return leading to further sampling. Thus,
throwing good money after bad can readily be an optimal response to the
increased option value of a high variance.
In most projects, there is uncertainty, and restarting after
stopping entails costs, making the option to continue valuable. This is
certainly the case for nuclear power plants, for example. Shutting down
a nuclear reactor requires dismantling or entombment and the costs of
restarting are extremely high. Moreover, the variance of energy prices
has been quite large. The option of maintaining nuclear plants is
therefore potentially valuable. Low returns from nuclear power in the
1970s and 1980s might have been a consequence of the large variance,
suggesting a high option value of maintaining nuclear plants. This may
in part explain the evidence (reported by De Bondt and Makhija 1988)
that managers of utilities at the time were so reluctant to shut down
seemingly unprofitable plants.
IV. REPUTATIONAL CONCERNS
Agents may also rationally react to sunk costs because of
reputational concerns. There are two main classes of relevant
reputational concerns: a reputation for commitment and a reputation for
ability.
A. Reputation for Commitment
Refusing to abandon projects with large sunk costs might be
rational because it creates a reputation for commitment. In a team
situation, should one agent abandon a joint project, the other team
members suffer as well. In such a complementary situation, the
willingness to persist with projects with large sunk costs might act as
a commitment, inducing investment by the other team members.
For example, in cartels and in marriage, an important aspect of the
incentive to participate and invest in the relationship is the belief
that the other party will stay in the relationship. If a member of an
illegal price-fixing cartel seems likely to confess to the government in
exchange for immunity from prosecution, the other cartel members may
race to be first to confess since only the first gets immunity (in
Europe, such immunity is called "leniency"). Similarly, a
spouse who loses faith in the long-term prospects of a marriage invests
less in the relationship, thereby reducing the gains from partnership,
potentially dooming the relationship. In both cases, beliefs about the
future viability matter to the success of the relationship, and there is
the potential for self-fulfilling optimistic and pessimistic beliefs.
In such a situation, individuals may rationally select others who
stay in the relationship beyond the point of individual rationality, if
such a commitment is possible. Indeed, ex ante it is rational to
construct exit barriers like costly and difficult divorce laws, so as to
reduce early exit. Such exit barriers might be behavioral as well as
legal. If an individual can develop a reputation for sticking in a
relationship beyond the break-even point, it would make that individual
a more desirable partner and thus enhance the set of available partners
as well as encourage greater and longer lasting investment by the chosen
partner.
One way of creating such a reputation is to act as if one cares
about sunk costs. In some sense, the history of a relationship is a sunk
cost (or benefit); if a person conditions on this history in a way that
makes him or her stay in relationships that have a 0 or slightly
negative expected value going forward, the person has created an exit
barrier.
This logic establishes the value of conditioning on sunk costs, or,
more realistically, sunk benefits, in the context of coinvestment and
partnership selection. An individual who uses the logic of "stay in
the relationship until the total value, including the sunk value,
generated by the relationship is zero" will be a more desirable
partner than the individual who leaves when the value going forward is
0. We now formalize this concept using a simple two-period model that
sets aside consideration of selection.
An agent matches with another agent, possibly for two periods. The
match is an agreement to share the sum of payoffs equally and therefore
the matched agents maximize their joint payoffs. In Period 1, both
agents sink investments x and y, respectively, which produce returns for
each of 1/2 [square root of xy], and cost 1/2 [x.sup.2] and 1/2
[y.sup.2], respectively. Investment only occurs in the first period. The
returns are repeated in the second period, provided both agents remain
in the relationship. In Period 2, with probability p, each agent is
offered the opportunity to break the relationship for the return V. The
outside offers to agents are independent. Each agent learns whether or
not he or she has an outside offer (but does not learn whether or not
the other has one) and then chooses whether or not to breach the
relationship. If one agent takes an outside offer but the other agent
does not receive one, the latter obtains zero. For each agent, breaching
the relationship also entails a reputation cost [rho], as it reduces the
agent's reputation for commitment and desirability as a partner in
future matches.
If both agents breach when given the opportunity to do so in Period
2, then the probability that both agents breach in Period 2 is
[p.sup.2], the probability that exactly one agent breaches is 21(1 - p),
and the probability that no agent breaches is [(1-p).sup.2]. Thus,
ignoring discounting, the sum of payoffs is u = (1 + [(1-p).sup.2]).
[square root of (xy)] + 2p (V -[rho]) -1/2 [x.sup.2] - 1/2 [y.sup.2],
which is maximized when x = y = 1/2 (1 + [(1 - p).sup.2]). An agent who
breaches receives V - [rho] in Period 2. An agent who does not breach
receives 1/2 [square root of xy] = 1/4 (1 + [(1 - p).sup.2]) in Period 2
if the other agent does not breach, which happens with probability 1 -
p, and receives 0 if the other agent breaches, which happens with
probability p, under the hypothesis that the other agent breaches given
the opportunity to do so. Thus, an agent who does not breach in Period 2
receives 1/2 [square root of xy] (1 -p) = 1/4 [(1 - p).sup.2]) (1 - p)
if the other agent breaches given the opportunity to do so. Therefore,
breaching is subgame perfect if V- [rho]> 1/4 (1 + [(1-p).sup.2]) (1
p).
If neither agent breaches given the opportunity to do so, then the
sum of payoffs is u = (2 [square root of xy]) - 1/2 [x.sup.2] - 1/2
[y.sup.2], which is maximized when x = y = 1. In this case, an agent who
does not breach receives 1/2 [square root of xy] = 1/2 in Period 2 given
that the other agent does not breach in Period 2. Thus, not breaching is
subgame perfect if V - [rho] < 1/2.
Consequently, if 1/2 > V - [rho] > 1/4 (1 +[(1 - p).sup.2])
(1 - p), then there are two subgame perfect equilibria, one with
breaching and the other without breaching. The "no-breaching"
equilibrium offers both parties higher payoffs. It results from
self-fulfilling optimistic beliefs. Given that the agents expect each
other not to breach in Period 2, they invest more in Period 1, which in
turn makes them want to continue (escalate) the relationship in Period
2. On the other hand, the breaching equilibrium results from
self-fulfilling pessimistic beliefs. Given that the agents expect each
other to breach in Period 2, they invest less in Period 1, and as a
consequence, they do not have sufficient incentive to continue the
relationship in Period 2. Note that looking across these two equilibria,
one would see escalation of commitment: when the investment is small,
the relationship breaks up and when the investment is large, the
relationship continues. If one took a sample of similar relationships,
some might be in the breaching equilibrium, where little is invested and
the relationship dissolves, while some might be in the no-breaching
equilibrium, where a lot is invested and the relationship lasts. Then,
if one regressed the probability of continuation on the amount invested,
one would obtain a positive correlation.
In situations where the reputation cost p from breaching the
relationship is large enough that V - [rho]< 1/4
(1+[(1-p).sup.2])(1-p), only the no-breaching equilibrium is subgame
perfect. Thus, rational concerns about reputation for commitment might
eliminate the breaching equilibrium. The agents might rationally avoid
breaching the relationship even when a great outside option presents
itself because they want to protect their reputation for commitment,
which makes both agents invest more initially, which in turn reduces
both agents incentives to breach when an outside option arises, leading
to the better, no-breaching equilibrium.
On the other hand, in situations where the reputation cost 9 of
breaching is low enough that V - [rho] > 1/2, breaching is the only
subgame perfect equilibrium. In this case, the total gains from trade
are [u.sup.*] = 1/4 [(1+[(1-p).sup.2]).sup.2] + 2p (V - [rho]). This
function is decreasing around p = 0 unless V - [rho] exceeds 1. That is,
a slight possibility of breach is collectively harmful; both agents
would be ex ante better off if they could prevent breach when V- [rho]
< 1, which holds as long as the reputation cost [rho] of breaching is
not too small. In this model, a tendency to stay in the relationship due
to a large sunk investment would be beneficial to each party. It would
be beneficial for an agent because of the effort it would induce in the
other agent, as well as for the increase in the agent's own effort,
even when the returns are shared between them. Any mechanism for
commitment to stay in the relationship even when the relationship has a
negative expected value going forward would serve the agents well.
B. Reputation for Ability
Abandoning a project may also reveal an agent as a poor forecaster,
leading agents to rationally persist with unprofitable projects to
conceal their poor skills. This argument has already been made formally
by several authors, most notably Kanodia, Bushman, and Dickhaut (1989),
Prendergast and Stole (1996), and Camerer and Weber (1999).
These models share the following features. Managers choose
projects, acquire private information about the productivity of the
projects while carrying them out, and choose how much more to invest in
them in light of this information. The quality of the private
information that they acquire is related to their unobservable ability.
Managers learn the productivity of projects more quickly, and choose
more productive projects if their ability is higher. Employers
rationally make inferences about their ability from their investment
choices.
Because more able managers learn the productivity of projects more
quickly, they are more likely to have more productive projects and thus
are more likely to continue investing. Then, if managers stop investing
upon learning that the projects are not productive, employers draw a
negative inference about their ability, which in turn reduces their
earnings opportunities. Once they have started to invest, stopping
reveals that they were slow in learning the productivity of the
projects, which signals low ability. For this reason, managers may
rationally continue investing even after learning that the projects are
unprofitable. Employers might, of course, eventually find out that the
projects are unprofitable in which case the managers might be fired.
Nonetheless, managers might rationally continue to invest even after
learning that the projects are unprofitable, to delay being fired, as
long as they discount the future.
Employers would certainly prefer that their managers immediately
cease bad projects. They could prevent them from continuing bad projects
if they could credibly promise not to fire them if they stopped.
However, such a promise is usually not credible. If the managers stop,
the employers learn that the projects are likely bad, and therefore, the
managers who chose them likely have low ability in which case the
employers are often better off firing the managers.
Low ability managers start projects because there is always the
chance that they would be lucky and choose good ones. Once they start,
they do not want to stop if they learn that the projects are bad because
they want to delay a negative inference about their ability and the
associated loss in their earnings potential.
Career concerns might be especially powerful in explaining the
evidence that politicians often throw good money after bad. Politicians
are agents for the people and choose projects for the provision of
public goods and the protection of national interests. However, they
differ in their ability to choose good projects, receive private
information about the quality of their chosen projects, make public
decisions about whether to continue them, and continue to benefit from
being in power only if they can maintain a good reputation. Moreover,
politicians are in a position where they heavily discount the future if
their reelection is not assured. If they can maintain their reputation
until the reelection date, they may remain in power. If they learn some
time before the reelection date that one of their projects is bad, they
are likely to continue the project to avoid a reputation loss at least
until after the reelection.
Politicians might continue a bad project to delay a reputation loss
especially if they are more interested in remaining in power than
serving the public. Ironically, when ultimately the project is
discovered to be bad and they incur the reputation loss, some among them
who are especially crooked and calculating might even turn and argue, as
Khieu Samphan did (see the introductory quotation), that the public
should "let bygones be bygones" and ignore the sunk costs of
the failed project. However, it is not rational for voters to forget
their failure, even though its costs are sunk, because the failure is
indicative of a propensity to fail again in the future. Moreover,
politicians who argue, like Khieu Samphan, that a very large sunk cost,
such as more than one million lives lost, should be forgotten lose all
reputation for commitment, which also makes any continued political
relationship with them very difficult to justify.
Last, reputation concerns may in part explain some reactions to
sunk costs in consumption. People who buy an exercise machine that costs
thousands of dollars, and then only use it a few days, or buy season
tickets to the theater, and then only attend a few plays, might make
their lapse of judgment manifest to others (for example, to their
spouse) and lose their reputation for making smart consumption choices.
To avoid or delay the reputation loss, they might rationally make
greater use of their past purchases than they would otherwise want to.
V. FINANCIAL AND TIME CONSTRAINTS
We have seen that moral hazard in the form of career concerns can
lead managers to persist with unprofitable projects. In general, moral
hazard and asymmetric information can create a host of managerial
problems to which firms rationally respond by imposing financial
constraints on managers. Abundant theoretical literature in corporate
finance shows that imposing financial constraints on firm managers
improves agency problems (Hart and Moore 1995; Lewis and Sappington
1989; Myers and Majluf 1984; Stiglitz and Weiss 1981). The theoretical
conclusion finds overwhelming empirical support, and only a small
fraction of business investment is funded by borrowing (Fazzari and
Athey 1987; Fazzari and Petersen 1993; Love 2003). When managers face
financial constraints, sunk costs must influence firm investments simply
because of budgets.
Firms with financial constraints might rationally react to sunk
costs by investing more in a project, rather than less, because the
ability to undertake alternative investments declines in the level of
sunk costs. Consider the following simple model. A firm with a budget of
B > 0 dollars is engaged in an investment opportunity, Project 1,
which requires paying a fixed cost [M.sub.0] > 0 before yielding a
rate of return of [R.sub.1] > 0 on every dollar spent beyond
[M.sub.0]. The firm is making payments in increments across time. Now
suppose that a better investment opportunity, Project 2, arises
unexpectedly. Project 2 is better than Project 1 in the sense that it
has the same fixed cost [M.sub.0] but a higher rate of return [R.sub.2]
> [R.sub.1]. Project 2 arises unexpectedly in the sense that,
initially, the probability that it would arise was low enough that the
firm found it worthwhile to start Project 1 (instead of waiting for
Project 2).
Let [M.sub.1] > 0 be the amount that the firm has already sunk
into Project 1 at the time that Project 2 arises. If [M.sub.1] >
[M.sub.0] then the firm switches to Project 2 if and only if (B -
[M.sub.1]) [R.sub.1] < (B - [M.sub.0] - [M.sub.1])[R.sub.2] or
equivalently [M.sub.0][R.sub.2] < (B- [M.sub.1])([R.sub.2]
[R.sub.1]). If [M.sub.1] < [M.sub.0] then the firm switches to
Project 2 if and only if (B - [M.sub.0])[R.sub.1] < (B - [M.sub.0] -
[M.sub.1])[R.sub.2] or equivalently [M.sub.1][R.sub.2] < (B -
[M.sub.0])([R.sub.2] - [R.sub.1]). In either case, the firm rationally
continues with Project 1 (the inequality is not satisfied) if the amount
[M.sub.1] that the firm has already sunk into Project 1 is sufficiently
large and switches to Project 2 (the inequality is satisfied) if
[M.sub.1] is sufficiently small. The firm also continues with Project 1
if the fixed cost [M.sub.0] to obtain a return on a project is
sufficiently large or if the firm's budget B is sufficiently small.
Given limited resources, if the firm has already sunk more
resources into the current project then the value of the option to start
a new project if it arises is lower relative to the value of the option
to continue the current project because fewer resources are left over to
bring any new project to fruition and more resources have already been
spent to bring the current project to fruition. Therefore, the
firm's incentive to continue investing in the current project is
higher the more resources it has already sunk into the project.
The above model might be germane to several apparent sunk cost
fallacies. It might explain why businesses sometimes stick with projects
that no longer appear to be the best choice. For example, an aircraft
company that had started a project to develop a radar-blind bomber plane
might seem overly reluctant to switch to developing a radar-blank
fighter plane if stealth fighters are suddenly in much greater demand;
but their reluctance might be rational because they might have a limited
budget, might have already spent hundreds of millions of dollars on
developing a cost-effective bomber, and would have to pay another large
fixed cost to develop a cost-effective fighter instead.
Resource constraints may explain apparent sunk costs fallacies not
only in business investment but also in other kinds of investment, for
example, in careers. People who have already invested a lot of money and
time on legal education, only to learn that a career in law would not
interest them much, might nonetheless persist in this career path
instead of switching to another one, such as becoming a doctor, even
though a career in medicine might now interest them more, because
becoming a doctor requires years in medical school, and they might have
already exhausted most of their time, and opportunities for student
loans, on their legal education.
With a resource constraint, an individual can only switch to a new
project a limited number of times since starting a new project is
costly. However, with only one more switch possible, starting a new
(better) project entails foreclosing the option to start a new (even
better) project in the future and thus would not be a rational choice
unless the gains were sufficiently large--there is substantial
"lock-in" even on the penultimate chance. However, using
backward induction, abandoning the third-to-last project means moving to
the penultimate one and its substantial lock-in, which means it is
suboptimal to abandon the third-to-last project unless the gains are
large, and so forth. Ultimately, one should not abandon a project for a
small expected gain, which entails rejecting better opportunities to
continue with the existing project.
In general, individuals have limited time to devote to investment
in projects and a limited number of attempts at new projects. As the
time remaining shrinks, individuals might rationally be more reluctant
to abandon current projects to start new ones. Consider the following
general model. Time is discrete, with periods 0, 1, 2, ..., T. At the
start of period t, the agent will have an existing project of type v.
The agent can stay with the project or choose a new project. Starting a
new project means ending the old project and the old project is never
recoverable once ended. New projects have a type, which is a random draw
from a distribution G with density g. This distribution is assumed to
have a well-defined mean. A project of type v produces v in every period
it is operated. The agent is risk neutral.
Because old projects are not recoverable, the agent will use a
cutoff strategy and draw a new project if the existing project is worse
than a critical value. Denote the critical value at time t by [c.sub.t].
The agent's utility at the start of period t is [U.sub.t](v) =
max{v + [U.sub.t + 1](V), E(v + [U.sub.t + 1] (v))}. Discounting is
assumed away for simplicity. Let [mu] be the mean. It is readily seen
that the last critical value is [c.sub.T] = [mu]. In the Appendix, we
prove that the critical values satisfy:
(*) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Moreover, the sequence [c.sub.t] is decreasing over time, ending at
[mu]. Thus, as the time remaining becomes shorter, the agent becomes
progressively more willing to stay with the existing project.
When G is uniform on [0, 1], the sequence is readily computed, and
Figure 1 shows the critical values in the last 1,000 time periods for
this case. The cutoffs decrease steadily for many periods and then drop
rapidly as the last period approaches.
Intuitively, with many periods remaining, if individuals switch to
another project and get a bad draw then there is ample time for them to
make up for it by switching again until the draw is better. But with
only a few periods remaining, there is little time to make up for a bad
draw. Another way to express the intuition for the result is that with
many periods remaining, individuals can amortize the cost of
experimentation over many periods. But with few periods remaining, they
can only amortize the experimentation cost over a few periods; and with
only one period remaining, they cannot amortize it at all. Thus, as the
time remaining shrinks, individuals become rationally more reluctant to
abandon current projects.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
This logic might also help explain instances of apparent escalation
of commitment. For example, people have limited time to invest in
education because ability to learn deteriorates rapidly after a certain
age. As the time they have remaining shrinks, they might rationally
become more reluctant to switch fields of study (even if their
satisfaction with their current field of study is not great) because
they have less time remaining to amortize the cost of experimenting with
new fields of study.
VI. CONCLUSIONS
In a world of uncertainty, future prospects are informed by past
decisions. In a world of scarce resources and finite time, future
prospects are limited by past decisions. In a world of social
interaction, future prospects are determined by the reputation that is
determined by past decisions. Therefore, reacting to past decisions, and
the sunk costs that they have entailed, is often rational.
In this article, we have shown that people might rationally invest
more if they have invested more in the past because greater past
investments often indicate that success is closer at hand and often
reduce the ability or willingness to undertake alternative investments
given the presence of financial and time constraints. We have shown that
people might rationally throw good money after bad, either because of
the high risks, and therefore high option values of continuing to
invest, which large losses often indicate, or to avoid immediately
losing their reputation for smart investment choices. And we have shown
that people might rationally react to sunk costs to create a reputation
for commitment, which tends to improve their welfare in joint investment
situations, by encouraging others to choose them as partners, and their
partners to invest more.
In addition, any of these reasons could be subject to evolutionary
selection; that is, people who are hard wired to condition their
behavior on sunk costs in a given set of situations could do better than
people who are not, so that a preference for conditioning on sunk costs
might prosper. If the target of evolutionary selection permits it,
responding to sunk costs would be rational given such a preference. An
evolutionary selection argument has the advantage that people might
occasionally condition on sunk costs even when it is disadvantageous to
do so because, on average, it is advantageous, thus accommodating
occasional demonstrably irrational behavior.
While we have argued that sunk cost effects have a rational
explanation, there is also a behavioral explanation for sunk cost
effects originally proposed by Thaler (1980) based on the prospect
theory of Kahneman and Tversky (1979). Under this theory, people react
to losses by investing more because they have loss aversion. The result
is explained by a property of preferences. In contrast, we have derived
the result from the principles of rationality (Bayesian inference and
constrained and dynamic optimization) without building it directly into
the preferences. Combining our rational explanation with evolutionary
pressures on preferences would reconcile the rational and behavioral
approaches to the question.
Although reacting to sunk costs is rational in many situations,
ignoring sunk costs is rational in others. According to our models, it
is a requirement of rationality to ignore sunk costs only in situations
in which past investments are not informative, reputation concerns are
unimportant, and budget constraints are not salient.
There is no clear evidence that people react to sunk costs in such
situations and some evidence that they do not. Most of the existing
empirical work has not controlled for changing hazards, option values,
reputations for ability and commitment, and budget constraints. We are
aware of only one study in which several of these factors are
eliminated--Friedman et al. (2007). In an experimental environment
without option value or reputation considerations, the authors find only
very small and statistically insignificant sunk cost effects in the
majority of their treatments, consistent with the rational theory
presented here.
ABBREVIATION
NPV: Net Present Value
doi: 10.1111/j.1465-7295.2008.00184.x
APPENDIX A
In this appendix, we derive Equation (*) in the text, which is the
solution to the last model that we develop in Section V. In the model,
at the start of the last period, an agent with project v is better off
with a new project if v is less than the mean project value,
(A1) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Thus, [C.sub.T] = [mu]. The agent's utility at the start of
period T is [U.sub.T](v) = max{v, [C.sub.T]}, which has expected value
over v of
(A2) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
This forms the base of an induction. The characterization of the
induction is that the agent uses the critical value:
(A3) [c.sub.T] = [mu] + [EU.sub.t+1]/T - t + 1
and
(A4) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Note this is trivially satisfied at t = T.
First, we show that this induction formula implies that the
sequence [c.sub.t] is decreasing in t. We have that [c.sub.t] >
[c.sub.t + 1] if and only if
(A5) [mu] + [EU.sub.t+1]/T-t+1 [greater than or equal to] [mu] +
[EU.sub.t+2]/T - t
if and only if
(A6) ([mu] + [EU.sub.t+1])(T - t) [greater than or equal to]([mu] +
[EU.sub.t+2])(T-t+1)
if and only if
(A7) [EU.sub.t+1] [greater than or equal to] 1/T-t [mu] + T -
t+1/T-t [EU.sub.t+2].
This is automatically satisfied because [EU.sub.1 + 1] [greater
than or equal to] [mu] + [EU.sub.1 + 2], a fact that is obvious from
[U.sub.t] (v) = max {v + [U.sub.t+1](v), E(v + [U.sub.t + 1](v))}.
Because [c.sub.t] is a decreasing sequence, if v > [c.sub.t] then v
> [c.sub.s] for all s > t. This simplifies the problem because it
means that if the agent does not choose a new project at t. the agent
never chooses a new project.
To complete the induction, note that
(A8) [U.sub.t-1}(v) = max{v + [U.sub.t](v),E(v + [U.sub.t](v))} =
max{(T - t+2)v, [mu]+ [EU.sub.t](v)}.
Thus, the critical value satisfies
(A9) [c.sub.t] = [mu] + [EU.sub.t]/T - t + 2
which is consistent with the induction hypothesis. Last,
(A10) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
This completes the induction.
The induction on the critical values simplifies:
(A11) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
with [c.sub.T] = [mu].
If G is uniform on [0, 1], the sequence is:
(A12) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Figure 1 in the text plots these critical values for T = 1,000.
REFERENCES
Arkes, H. R., and C. Blumer. "The Psychology of Sunk
Cost." Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 35,
1985, 124-40.
Camerer, C. F., and R. A. Weber. "The Econometrics and
Behavioral Economics of Escalation of Commitment: A Re-examination of
Staw and Hoang's NBA Data." Journal of Economic Behavior and
Organization, 39, 1999, 59-82.
Carmichael, L., and B. W. MacLeod. "Caring About Sunk Costs: A
Behavioral Solution to Holdup Problems With Small Stakes." Journal
of Law, Economics, and Organization, 19, 2003, 106-18.
De Bondt, W. F. M., and A. K. Makhija. "Throwing Good Money
After Bad? Nuclear Power Plant Investment Decisions and the Relevance of
Sunk Costs." Journal of Eeonomic Behavior and Organization, 10,
1988, 173-99.
Dixit, A. K. "Investment and Hysteresis." Journal of
Economic Perspectives, 6, 1992, 107-32.
Dixit, A. K., and R. S. Pindyck. Investment Under Uncertainty.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994.
Epstein, S. S. The Politics of Cancer Revisited. New York: East
Ridge Press, 1998.
Fazzari, S., and M. J. Athey. "Asymmetric Information,
Financing Constraints, and Investment." Review of Economies and
Statistics, 69, 1987, 481-87.
Fazzari, S., and B. Petersen. "Working Capital and Fixed
Investment: New Evidence on Financing Constraints." RAND Journal of
Economics, 24, 1993, 328-42.
Frank, R. H., and B. Bernanke. Principles of Microeconomics. 3rd
ed. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2006.
Friedman, D., K. Pommerenke, R. Lukose, G. Milam, and B. Huberman.
"Searching for the Sunk Cost Fallacy." Experimental Economics,
10, 2007, 79-104.
Garland, H., C. A. Sandefur, and A. C. Rogers. "Deescalation
of Commitment in Oil Exploration: When Sunk Costs and Negative Feedback
Coincide." Journal of Applied Psychology, 75, 1990, 721 27.
Hart, O., and J. Moore. "Debt and Seniority: An Analysis of
the Role of Hard Claims in Constraining Management." American
Economic Review, 85 1995, 567-85.
Heath, C. "Escalation and De-escalation of Commitment in
Response to Sunk Costs: The Role of Budgeting in Mental
Accounting." Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes,
62, 1995, 38-54.
Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky. "Prospect Theory: An Analysis of
Decision Under Risk." Econometrica, 47, 1979, 263-91.
Kanodia, C., R. Bushman, and J. Dickhaut. "Escalation Errors
and the Sunk Cost Effect: An Explanation Based on Reputation and
Information Asymmetries." Journal of Accounting Research, 27, 1989,
59-77.
Khan, B. A., S. B. Salter, and D. J. Sharp. "'Throwing
Good Money After Bad: A Comparison of Asian and Developed Country
Managerial Decision-Making in Sunk Cost Situations." Asian Pacific
Development Journal, 7, 2000, 105-20.
Lewis, T., and D. E. M. Sappington. "Countervailing Incentives
in Agency Problems." Journal of Economic Theory, 49, 1989, 294-313.
Love, 1. "Financial Development and Financing Constraints:
International Evidence from the Structural Investment Model."
Review of Financial Studies, 16, 2003, 765-91.
Mankiw, N. G. Principles of Microeconomies. 3rd ed. Mason, OH:
Thomson South-Western, 2004.
Mendelson, H., and P. Meza. "Amazon.com: Marching Toward
Profitability. "Stanford University Graduate School of Business
Case Number EC-25, 2001.
Myers, S., and N. S. Majluf. "Corporate Financing and
Investment Decisions when Firms Have Information that Investors Do Not
Have." Journal of Financial Economies, 13, 1984, 187-221.
Olson, J. E. The Northmen, Columbus and Cabot. 985-1503. New York:
Barnes and Noble, 1967.
Pindyck, R. S. "Irreversibility, Uncertainty, and
Investment." Journal of Economic Literature, 29, 1991, 1110-52.
Prendergast, C., and L. Stole. "Impetuous Youngsters and Jaded Old-Timers: Acquiring a Reputation for Learning." Journal of
Political Economy, 104, 1996, 1105-34.
Schwartz, B. "The Sunk-Cost Fallacy: Bush Falls Victim to a
Bad Argument for the War in Iraq." Slate, September 9, 2005.
Staw, B. M. "Knee-Deep in the Big Muddy: A Study of Escalating
Commitment to a Chosen Course of Action." Organizational Behavior
and Human Performance, 16, 1976, 27-44.
--. "The Escalation of Commitment to a Course of
Action.'" Academy of Management Review, 6, 1981, 577-87.
Staw, B. M., and H. Hoang. "Sunk Costs in the NBA: Why Draft
Order Affects Playing Time in Professional Basketball."
Administrative Science Quarterly, 40, 1995, 474-94.
Steele, D. R. "Nozick on Sunk Costs." Ethics, 106, 1996,
605-20.
Stiglitz, J. E., and A. Weiss. "Credit Rationing in Markets
with Imperfect Information." American Economic Review, 71, 1981,
393-410.
Teger, A. I. Too Much Invested to Quit. New York: Permagon, 1980.
Thaler, R. "Toward a Positive Theory of Consumer Choice."
Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1, 1980, 39-60.
--. Quasi-Rational Economics. New York: Russell Sage Foundation,
1991.
Walton, D. "The Sunk Cost Fallacy or Argument from
Waste." Argumentation, 16, 2002, 473-503.
Whyte, G. "Escalating Commitment in Individual and Group
Decision-Making." Organizational Behavior and Human Decision
Processes, 54, 1993, 430-55.
R. PRESTON MCAFEE, HUGO M. MIALON and SUE H. MIALON *
* We are grateful to two anonymous referees for helpful comments.
McAfee: Humanities and Social Sciences, California Institute of
Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125. Phone 626395-3476, Fax 626-793-4681,
E-mail
[email protected]
H. M. Mialon: Department of Economics, Emory University, Atlanta,
GA 30322-2240. Phone 404-408-8333, Fax 404-727-4639, E-mail
[email protected]
S. H. Mialon: Department of Economics, Emory University, Atlanta,
GA 30322-2240. Phone 404-712-8169, Fax 404727-4639, E-mail
[email protected]