首页    期刊浏览 2025年05月04日 星期日
登录注册

文章基本信息

  • 标题:Peg Birmingham: Hannah Arendt and Human Rights: The Predicament of Common Responsibility.
  • 作者:Berkowitz, Roger
  • 期刊名称:Philosophy in Review
  • 印刷版ISSN:1206-5269
  • 出版年度:2008
  • 期号:April
  • 语种:English
  • 出版社:University of Victoria
  • 摘要:Hannah Arendt and Human Rights: The Predicament of Common Responsibility.

Peg Birmingham: Hannah Arendt and Human Rights: The Predicament of Common Responsibility.


Berkowitz, Roger


Peg Birmingham

Hannah Arendt and Human Rights: The Predicament of Common Responsibility.

Bloomington: Indiana University Press 2007.

Pp. 176.

US$24.95 (paper ISBN-13: 978-0-253-21865-0).

Few formulas have so captivated political thinkers in recent times as Hannah Arendt's invocation of the 'right to have rights'. Arendt's readers have never tired of invoking her ambitious reformulation of human rights even as they have ceaselessly lamented her failure to offer a meaningful foundation for it. The signal contribution of Birmingham's book is her reconstruction of a coherent and convincing argument for Arendt's radical refoundation of human rights.

Birmingham's is a careful and profound reading of Arendt that should impact, for the better, both the burgeoning field of human rights and the more prosaic world of the Hannah Arendt industry. She states her thesis directly: 'Arendt's entire work can be read as an attempt to work out theoretically this fundamental right to have rights' (1). Dozens of books have been published recently that dutifully detail and bemoan the fact that there is no ground for human rights; Birmingham's book--despite its different genre--is a welcome remedy that argues, largely convincingly, that Arendt does develop just such a foundation.

The key to Arendt's re-formulation of human rights is based on her demand that humanity 'itself must guarantee the right to have rights' (6). What Birmingham sees is that Arendt never drops her call for a new law of humanity; instead, in her later work, she continues to explore the law of humanity under the heading of natality. By connecting Arendt's concept of natality to her guiding project of founding a right to have rights, Birmingham both deepens our understanding of Arendt and makes clear Arendt's importance to the human rights community.

Against the single-minded focus of Arendt scholars on the political and participatory understanding of natality as a principle of beginning, Birmingham sees that natality encompasses two related principles, the principle of beginning and the principle of givenness. Chapters 1 and 2 enrich the traditional account of natality through a sympathetic reading of Arendt's debt to Martin Heidegger and Franz Kafka. Birmingham shows that the freedom to begin is rooted in a specifically human temporality of mortality that is the ontological foundation of the right to have rights. The right to have rights is best understood not as a right in the legal sense of the term, but as a fundamental demand of being human, that one be born and die. To be born, she argues, is to be bound into a linguistic world; it is to be thrown into a world where we are abandoned in a space of beginning that is 'always open to something other than itself' (31). Human freedom, Birmingham argues, emerges from an obligation to oneself and others in the condition of natal vulnerability (61).

Birmingham develops her second and most original contribution in Chapter 3, 'The Principle of Givenness: Appearance, Singularity, and the Right to Have Rights'. Here Birmingham argues that natality means more than beginning; in addition, natality names the givenness of human being. Again Birmingham illuminates Arendt by exploring the source of her thinking in Heidegger, this time through Arendt's own critique of the discussion of physis in Heidegger's Anaximander fragment. Since 'physis is genesis, an unpredictable appearing,' it shares with natality a quality of an absolute beginning free of any cause or governing telos (84). The principle of givenness is an 'anarchic' principle that is '[c]ut off and adrift from any sovereign constituting power or foundation . . .' (86). Since each person is a radical beginning, human rights and the right to have rights 'includes the principle of givenness,' by which Arendt means the mere right to exist, to appear as a singular, alien, foreign and isolated individual (91). It is the obligation in the face of the alien that must be respected as part of the human that, according to Birmingham, underlies Arendt's guarantee of the right to have rights to every human being.

Since human existence, as physis, is cut off from any prior reason or ground, man is unjustifiable and thus vulnerable. Man stands alone as alien and strange. And this strangeness that attaches to man's natality both underlies Arendt's defense of plurality and her insistence that the right to have rights includes the right to be as you are. Birmingham does not make the connection, but this right to be as one is lies behind Arendt's passionate defense of a rich private sphere, including the rights of parents to send their children to segregated schools. Though much criticized, the Little Rock essay is, I think, at the core of the principle of givenness Birmingham highlights.

The first three chapters of this book offer a discourse-shifting reading of Arendt's work as providing an ontologically sound foundation for human rights, something that modern human rights discourse desperately needs. As strong as these chapters are, Chapter 4 seems a digression. Birmingham argues that Julia Kristeva's psychoanalytic concept of abjection is a 'necessary' aide to understanding Arendt's claim about the givenness of human difference (119). Why this foray into psychology (which Birmingham knows full well Arendt would not support) is necessary, is never clarified.

The short conclusion offers a preliminary inquiry into the institutional forms that Arendt discusses that might support her account of the right to have rights. The critique of sovereignty and the distinction between (dangerous) globalism and (promising) internationalism are suggestive, but the political potential of Birmingham's account is never carried through. This was not the goal of her book, and she generously points the way toward future scholarship in these areas. Short, clearly organized, and densely written, this book is a must-read for anyone interested in thinking deeply about human rights.

Roger Berkowitz

Bard College
联系我们|关于我们|网站声明
国家哲学社会科学文献中心版权所有