Cicero, Aquinas, and contemporary issues in natural law theory.
Seagrave, S. Adam
THE ADVENT OF THE "NEW NATURAL LAW" THEORY in the latter
half of the twentieth century has had the welcome effect of inviting St.
Thomas into discussion with contemporary moral, legal, and political
philosophy. With Finnis's seminal work, a broadly Thomistic natural
law was rendered not only compatible with contemporary analytic
philosophy and jurisprudence, but foundational with respect to the
natural rights that define the liberal tradition. (1) The impact of
Finnis's ambitious synthesis of characteristically modern insights
with Thomistic natural law, while it has proceeded in connection with a
larger movement within post-Vatican II Catholicism, has become
increasingly relevant to purely secular debates within contemporary
liberalism. This impact may be clearly seen in a recent attempt to
construct a "natural law liberalism" which promises to include
the core ideas of each tradition within a single, coherent political
philosophy. (2)
Amidst the fervor in some scholarly circles to render Thomistic
natural law theory relevant to a contemporary context imbued with the
doctrines of liberalism and guided by the demands of analytical rigor,
however, this natural law theory has itself been largely uprooted from
its classical foundation. This uprooting is significant primarily
because Thomistic natural law theory becomes more, rather than less,
persuasive when it is viewed in light of its classical foundation. In
spite of this, the interpretation of St. Thomas's so-called
"Treatise on Law" (and conscious departures from it) by the
new natural law theorists largely presupposes the absence of such a
foundation. (3) This presupposition is, moreover, not unfounded. The two
most obvious candidates for a foundational role in Thomistic natural law
from classical antiquity, Aristotle and Cicero, have been widely
pronounced unfit for the task. The term "natural law" is
entirely absent from Aristotle's works, and the very notion appears
to be largely alien to his thought. (4) Although references to the
"natural law" abound in Cicero's works, this natural law
appears to be little more than a transmission of Stoic ideas; (5) and
while St. Thomas's natural law doctrine may indeed have Stoic
resonances, the cosmology which grounds the Stoic natural law was
clearly superseded in St. Thomas's work by Christian doctrines.
From these considerations it would appear that St. Thomas's natural
law is less the culmination of a preceding tradition than the prototype
of an entirely new natural law doctrine centered upon the famous theory
of the "inclinations." (6)
The failure to locate significant preChristian influences on St.
Thomas's natural law has, moreover, lent substantial support to
antinatural law arguments. The question posed by Strauss in Natural
Right and History accurately encapsulates the starting-point for such
arguments: "one would be forced to wonder ... whether the natural
law as Thomas Aquinas understands it is natural law strictly speaking,
that is, a law knowable to the unassisted human mind, to the human mind
which is not illumined by divine revelation." (7) If Thomistic
natural law is coextensive with Christian belief, it is difficult to
avoid answering this question in the negative. Finnis himself is
irresistibly led to this conclusion by presenting a theory of natural
law independent of "the question of God's existence or nature
or will;" (8) without this reference to God, the natural law is
"only analogically law." (9)
From this verdict, it seems that the debate between contemporary
defenders and opponents of natural law theory is in fact characterized
by fundamental agreement. The question of "whether the natural law
exists" has been widely closed; it is now asked "whether
something natural law-like exists," "whether there is a
natural and objective standard for human action," (10) or even
"whether certain ideas associated with the natural law may be
beneficial or useful in a contemporary liberal context." (11) The
quest for a natural law strictly speaking has been all but abandoned;
the "natural law" has become a mere Christian-Aristotelian
idiom, (12) retained out of deference to its historical lineage but
weakened in meaning by the force of modern analytical inquiry.
The intention of this paper is to reopen the question of the
existence of a natural law in the strict sense, and renew the quest for
its understanding, by establishing a substantial basis for Thomistic
natural law theory in preChristian, classical philosophy. The
establishment of such a basis lends support to the contention, of
central importance for understanding St. Thomas's natural law, that
a Thomistic natural law theory need not rely on specifically Christian
assumptions or beliefs. The crucial step in the argument for such a
basis lies in a proper appreciation of Cicero's active and
distinctive role in the formation of the natural law tradition. Contrary
to widely accepted interpretations of Cicero's works, Cicero's
natural law is not a mere transmission of or elaboration upon Stoic
ideas. While Cicero undoubtedly draws upon these ideas, a careful
attentiveness to the natural law theory he presents reveals a much
closer affinity to Aristotle's moral philosophy. Prior to the
advent of Christianity and long before the appearance of St.
Thomas's Summa, Cicero had derived a coherent and persuasive, if
somewhat rudimentary, natural law theory from an Aristotelian
understanding of human nature. St. Thomas's natural law is both
more accurately understood and more persuasive when it is viewed as a
continuation and culmination of this Ciceronian-Aristotelian natural law
than as the inchoate expression of a "new" natural law.
I
Although Cicero has always been esteemed for his achievements in
the field of rhetoric, it is only in recent years that he has begun to
regain the scholarly appreciation which he received in the Middle Ages
for his achievements in political philosophy. (13) Despite this renewed
attention to Cicero as a political philosopher in his own right,
Cicero's treatment of the natural law is still regarded as largely
secondhand and the degree to which he presents his own natural law
theory is frequently questioned.
The secondhand characterization involves some version of the
"conventional wisdom that Cicero was repeating Stoic ideas"
(14) in his statements regarding the natural law. Characterizing
Cicero's natural law theory in this way exposes this theory to a
number of difficulties. The primary difficulty involves the Stoic
cosmology which serves as the foundation for the natural law, a
cosmology which had been discredited by Cicero himself in his De Natura
Deoram and has been widely discarded since Cicero's time. If
Cicero's natural law theory is little more than a transmission of
the Stoic natural law, with its accompanying dubious cosmology,
Cicero's natural law cannot have been taken very seriously by the
Christian St. Thomas Aquinas and cannot be persuasive in the
contemporary context. Even when the Stoic characterization of
Cicero's natural law is not accepted in its precise form, however,
Cicero's conception of the natural law is regarded at most as a
moderated or "transformed" (15) Stoicism rather than as a
credible doctrine in itself which is influenced by Stoic ideas.
The plausibility of this characterization stems from Cicero's
apparent reluctance to speak in his own voice in his writings. In the De
Re Publica, Cicero himself speaks only through prefaces, leaving the
dialogue primarily to Scipio, Laelius, and Philus. In the De Legibus,
although Cicero himself appears as the primary interlocutor, he
explicitly indicates that he is following the pattern set by Plato in
the overall plan of his work by devoting separate but interrelated
dialogues to the "Republic" and its "Laws." (16) In
the first book, moreover, Cicero states that he is "following the
method of the philosophers--not those of former times, but those who
have built workshops, so to speak, for the production of wisdom,"
(17) namely, the Stoics. (18) That Cicero was conscious of his tendency
to appear to "meekly ... accept the authority of others" (19)
in his writings is evidenced by the reproach he puts in the mouth of
Atticus at this juncture of the dialogue. Atticus anticipates the manner
in which Cicero will be interpreted by scholars hundreds of years later
by accusing Cicero of being "the kind of man not to follow [his]
own judgment in a debate." (20) Cicero's terse reply serves as
a stern warning to his readers: Non semper, Tite.
In the De Finibus, Cicero relates a series of dialogues in each of
which he himself is present as a participant, although the entire work
is addressed to Brutus for his approval. In each dialogue, moreover,
Cicero is concerned not simply with presenting his own views, but rather
with critically evaluating those of the Epicureans, Stoics, and
Peripatetics. In refuting the Epicureans, Cicero takes a largely Stoic
position; responding to the Stoics, he adopts a Peripatetic perspective;
and in his brief criticism of the Peripatetics, Cicero again takes up
the Stoic viewpoint.
The De Officiis, though not presented in dialogue form, is
similarly directed to a particular addressee, in this case Cicero's
own son. In this work, Cicero again makes explicit his intention to
follow a particular school, the Stoics (and particularly Panaetius). The
manner in which Cicero qualifies this admission is, however, worthy of
note:
I shall, therefore, follow chiefly the Stoics, not as a translator,
but, as is my custom, I shall at my own option and discretion draw
from those sources in such measure and in such manner as shall suit
my purpose. (21)
This statement is relevant not only to a proper interpretation of
the De Officiis, but also to an interpretation of each of Cicero's
other allegedly secondhand works. By indicating that his general
"custom" involves a particular kind of "following,"
namely one which involves the exercise of "discretion" and
discrimination in a manner which suits his "purpose," Cicero
reiterates and clarifies his reply to Atticus in the De Legibus. Non
semper would not mean that Cicero usually follows others unreflectively
and occasionally brings his own understanding to bear; rather, Cicero
only repeats the opinions of others when they are relevant to the
"purpose" of his own exposition.
Considering this passage and others with similar purport, many
commentators have rejected the simplistic position that Cicero's
statements regarding the natural law are an unreflective regurgitation
of Stoic tenets. (22) The next question, however, of whether
Cicero's own purpose is to present a natural law teaching (in the
strict sense) is frequently answered in the negative. This answer
appears in two primary forms.
The first form depicts Cicero as reflecting the Middle Platonic
idea, espoused first by Antiochus of Ascalon, of a "transcendent
God who was the Lawgiver as well as the Father and Maker of the
world." (23) If a "transcendent God" is the immediate
source of the natural law, however, this law does not qualify as
strictly "natural;" (24) such a law would be properly termed
"divine" and only secondarily or metaphorically
"natural." According to this interpretation of Cicero's
natural law as a "divine" law, Cicero anticipates the more
explicit absorption of the natural law into theology which allegedly
occurs in the Christian Middle Ages. (25) If Cicero's natural law
is really a divine law for nature, it is not natural in the proper sense
of inhering in nature. (26) Therefore, Cicero's own purpose is not
to present a theory of the natural law, but rather to replace the Stoic
immanent natural law with a transcendently divine or eternal one.
The second form of answer follows, to some extent, on the
conclusion of the first. In the view of Strauss and others connected
with him, Cicero's ultimate purpose is to present the Stoic natural
law in a manner that reveals the incoherence of the natural law itself
and its incompatibility with the more credible doctrine of natural
right. (27) This involves an interpretation of Cicero in light of a
particular criticism of natural law theory, namely that it represents
the incoherent intersection of natural right and some form of divine or
eternal law. Cicero, perceiving that the notion of natural law cannot be
meaningfully distinguished from that of divine law, and further that
human affairs do not admit of "categorical" rules but must
instead be guided by the standard of natural right, (28) subtly rejects
his superficial statements regarding the natural law.
In the following discussion, I propose to return to the question of
whether Cicero does in fact present a genuine and coherent natural law
teaching as his own. I will argue that, across the various contexts in
which Cicero's statements on the subject appear, an underlying
continuity emerges which is rooted in an Aristotelian understanding of
nature. This understanding is developed in such a manner that law is
perceived as necessarily inhering in human nature and implied by its
very description.
The most frequently cited passage in Cicero's writings
relating to the natural law is that given by Laelius in the third book
of the De Re Publica. In responding to Philus' feigned attack on
the natural basis of law, Laelius states that
True law is right reason in agreement with nature; it is of
universal application, unchanging and everlasting; it summons to
duty by its commands, and averts from wrongdoing by its
prohibitions. And it does not lay its commands or prohibitions upon
good men in vain, though neither have any effect on the wicked. It
is a sin to try to alter this law, nor is it allowable to attempt
to repeal any part of it, and it is impossible to abolish it
entirely. We cannot be freed from its obligations by senate or
people, and we need not look outside ourselves for an expounder or
interpreter of it. (29)
Although this portion of Laelius' statement emphasizes the
"natural" character of the "true law," the latter
half of his exposition introduces some elements of ambiguity:
And there will not be different laws at Rome and at Athens, or
different laws now and in the future, but one eternal and
unchangeable law will be valid for all nations and all times, and
there will be one master and ruler, that is, God, over us all, for
he is the author of this law, its promulgator, and its enforcing
judge. Whoever is disobedient is fleeing from himself and denying
his human nature, and by reason of this very fact he will suffer
the worst penalties, even if he escapes what is commonly considered
punishment.
The mention of "God" as the "author,"
"promulgator," and "enforcing judge" of the true law
seems to establish this law as a properly divine one. This appears,
however, to contradict both the contention that "we need not look
outside ourselves" to discover the true law, and the assertion that
to controvert this law is not simply to disobey God, but to "deny
... human nature" which includes its own proper and effective
mechanism of enforcement.
Although much is made of the fact that this statement is given by
Laelius rather than Scipio or Cicero himself in his own name, this fact
does not by itself indicate Cicero's dissociation from the ideas
expressed therein. The relevant textual evidence in fact suggests
precisely the reverse.
In a rare break in the dialogue, Cicero, the narrator of De Re
Publica, describes the reception of Laelius' remarks among his
interlocutors: "After these words from Laelius, all expressed their
great pleasure in his remarks; but Scipio, whose delight went beyond
that of the rest, was almost carried away with enthusiasm." (30)
This passage mitigates, to a large extent, the interpretive difficulties
associated with relating the opinions of the particular characters in
the dialogue to Cicero himself. If "all" (apparently including
Philus the Academic Skeptic and erstwhile opponent of the natural law)
delighted in Laelius's speech, there is little opportunity to align
Cicero himself with another interlocutor in opposition to Laelius. This
is particularly apparent from the fact that Scipio, who is most commonly
taken to be Cicero's mouthpiece in the dialogue, is "carried
away with enthusiasm" at Laelius' remarks. Although Cicero
could have detached himself from the general approval of Laelius'
words by putting this passage in the voice of one of his characters, he
instead indicates that he takes Laelius's statements seriously by
momentarily interrupting the flow of the dialogue to interject his own
voice.
In arguing against the Epicureans in his own voice in the De
Finibus, moreover, Cicero cites Laelius' speech in the De Re
Publica with approval. (31) Also speaking in his own voice in the first
book of De Legibus, Cicero is primarily concerned with offering
additional arguments in support of Laelius's primary contention
that justice and law are rooted in nature. (32) While this evidence does
not demonstrate Cicero's unqualified identification with
Laelius' statements regarding the natural law, (33) it does
indicate that these statements, far from being subtly rejected by
Cicero, are largely consonant with his own opinions. The next task,
then, becomes that of showing how Laelius' extended definition may
be unpacked in a Ciceronian fashion.
The first question concerns the level of correspondence between
Laelius' description of "true law," or vera lex, and the
formulations which appear elsewhere in Cicero's writings as the
"law of nature," (34) "universal law" (35)
"supremeLaw," (36) and "the law of peoples." (37) In
the first book of De Legibus, each of these alternative formulations
emerges and is woven together by Cicero at the outset of his discussion.
In this context Cicero expresses the opinion of the "most learned
men" who define law as
the highest reason, implanted in Nature, which commands what
ought to be done and forbids the opposite. This reason, when
firmly fixed and fully developed in the human mind, is Law. (38)
This opinion, which seems correct to Cicero, (39) connects law with
the same "reason" and human nature which form the principles
of "true law" in Laelius' description. Shortly after this
definition, Cicero also connects the "highest reason" with
Laelius' notion of "right reason," (40) and introduces a
similar ambiguity by referring to the "God of transcendent
power" who rules over the community of gods and men. (41)
In developing Laelius' description of the "true
law," Cicero indicates that the various formulations noted above
all refer to the same law considered with respect to diverse relations.
This law is described as "true" and "supreme" in
order to distinguish it from the "crowd's definition of
law," that is, written decrees which are established by human
beings and deal largely with matters of detail. (42) It is described as
the "universal law" and the "law of peoples" since
it is not "confined" to any particular state or nation as is
the civil law. (43) It is most properly described as the "law of
nature," or the "natural law," since its very principle
of derivation lies in human nature. (44)
By deemphasizing this last relation of the law of human nature and
seizing upon the element of the divine in Cicero's account, it is
often argued that Cicero subtly dissociates himself from his statements
in the first book of De Legibus in much the same way as is thought to
occur in the De Re Publica. This argument avers that Cicero presents the
natural law in this context as a kind of "noble lie" that,
while useful "for political purposes," (45) is indefensible
from a philosophical standpoint. (46) In this case as in the former one,
the evidence of the text appears to controvert this assertion. Holton
himself quotes one such passage in which Cicero states that his
arguments for the natural law seem to him "usually and mostly"
correct. (47) Before embarking on his discussion of the natural law,
moreover, Cicero distinguishes his purpose in the De Legibus from that
of the common lawyer by stating that
while I do not consider that those who have applied themselves to
this profession have lacked a conception of universal law, yet they
have carried their studies of this civil law, as it is called, only
far enough to accomplish their purpose of being useful to the
people. Now all this amounts to little so far as learning is
concerned, though for practical purposes it is indispensable. (48)
This passage indicates that Cicero's "purpose" in
the De Legibus extends beyond what is "useful to the people"
and is not merely "practical;" he desires, rather, that it
will amount to something "so far as learning is concerned,"
that is, philosophically.
It is also important to note the role of the reference to the
divine in Cicero's account in the De Legibus as well as
Laelius' in the De Re Publica. In both places, this element is
appended to the substance of an argument from human nature itself.
Cicero's overarching concern is with "Nature's gifts to
man," (49) and while some indication of the probable source of
these gifts gives the discussion a certain fullness, these gifts are the
proper province not of theology but of "the deepest mysteries of
philosophy." (50) The "nature of Justice" and its origin
in Law "must be sought for in the nature of man." (51) The
divine element is presented not as a necessary premise but as a probable
"theory" which may be advanced to supplement an examination of
the nature of man. (52)
Although Cicero appears to require Atticus's curious admission
of the divine governance of nature for his subsequent discussion of the
natural law, both the manner in which Cicero makes his appeal and that
in which it is admitted by his Epicurean friend supports the inessential
role of the idea of a transcendent God in coming to a basic
understanding of nature itself. (53) Cicero's appeal begins with
the postulated existence of the "might of the immortal gods,"
but is subsequently diluted to more modest formulations in terms of
"nature, reason, power, mind," and "will." (54)
Atticus's acquiescence to this appeal, moreover, does not occur in
an inexplicable fashion. The precise reason Atticus gives for accepting
Cicero's claim lies in "the singing of the birds about us and
the babbling of the streams," (55) that is, in an observation of
natural phenomena. Therefore, in light of the fact that Cicero's
discussion of the natural law does not include the existence of God as a
necessary logical premise, (56) Atticus may have granted Cicero only the
concept of "nature" which, in actuality, is all that Cicero
really required in the first place.
It is to the concept of human nature in particular, and reason as
its distinguishing feature, that we now must turn in order to show how
it becomes associated with "law" in Cicero's writings.
The foundation of this concept, for Cicero, lies in the specific place
of human beings within a hierarchy of natures. In the beginning of the
De Officiis, Cicero describes the natural characteristics and
"instincts" of "every species of living creature."
(57) These instincts primarily include self-preservation and
reproduction, along with other instincts which are instrumental to these
two. Although man possesses these animal impulses, he also exhibits the
"marked difference" of "reason." (58)
This description echoes Cicero's statement in the De Legibus
that "reason, which alone raises us above the level of the beasts
... is certainly common to us all." (59) In both accounts, Cicero
begins by descriptively listing the proper capacities and inclinations
inherent in reason. Reason's proper capacities include the ability
"to draw inferences," (60) "to discuss and solve
problems," (61) "perceive the causes of things," (62) and
"connect and associate the present and the future." (63) The
proper inclinations of reason include the impulse to form communities
with other human beings, to "provide a store of things" (64)
both for himself and others in his care, and to "search after
truth." (65)
Cicero also follows this discussion of reason in both accounts with
a similarly descriptive one of the "evil tendencies" (66)
inherent in human nature. These tendencies which run counter to the good
of reason are generally subsumed under the heading of "sensual
pleasure." (67) Sensual pleasure, moreover, is associated with
"cattle and other beasts" which are "impelled"
towards its pursuit in an irrational and unreflective manner. (68)
The crucial point here is that both inclinations, those pertaining
to reason and those pertaining to the sensual appetite, are natural to
human beings. (69) The problem of deciding between these inclinations in
correctly determining one's actions does not exist for Cicero for
the simple reason that man's rational aspect is clearly superior to
his animal one. Thus Cicero explicates the virtue of
"propriety" and its corresponding "duty," which
involves the general one to live in agreement with nature, by stating
that
the essential activity of the spirit and also nature is twofold:
one force is appetite ... which impels a man this way and that; the
other is reason, which teaches and explains what should be done and
what should be left undone. The result is that reason commands,
appetite obeys. (70)
Although this passage appears in the context of Cicero's
discussion of the virtues, it is strikingly reminiscent of many
formulations of the natural law throughout Cicero's writings. One
is immediately reminded of Laelius's definition: "True law is
right reason in agreement with nature ... it summons to duty by its
commands, and averts from wrongdoing by its prohibitions." For
human beings, living in agreement with nature simultaneously implies the
presence of virtue and obedience to the natural law.
Cicero thus derives both the natural law and the Virtues from the
single "fountain-head" of human nature. (71) This derivation
initially appears to be a prime example of the "naturalistic
fallacy" that, according to some, decisively refutes "the most
popular image of natural law" and necessitates the project of the
new natural law theorists. (72) Cicero does, in effect, build a
"normative" theory of the virtues and the natural law using
only a "descriptive" account of human nature. It will be
remembered, however, that Cicero's descriptive account of human
nature involved two types of "facts" existing in a complex
relationship of hierarchical order and potential opposition. The first
aspect of this relationship concerns the superiority of reason and its
determinations to the blind impulses of the sensual appetite. The second
expresses the power of the sensual appetite to reverse this hierarchy
and influence human action in spite of reason's determinations.
From reason's capacity for reflection and deliberation, as well as
its impulse to direct and restrain the potentially rebellious passions,
emerges the human possibility of choice.
The proper notion of law arises out of this descriptive account in
two related ways. In the first way, human nature implies an inherent law
from the very fact that its proper inclinations are only carried from
potentiality into actuality in accordance with the contingent power of
choice. (73) In other words, the "is" of human nature is in a
perpetual state of potential conflict with the "is" of
particular human actions. The facts of human nature include the primary
inclination or general rule to act in accordance with this nature; this
general rule becomes a command when it confronts the indeterminacy of
choice.
The rule of acting in accordance with human nature possesses the
form of a command, rather than a counsel or recommendation, since it
includes the threat of punishment and the promise of reward (the proper
effects of the notion of a command). (74) The punishment threatened by
the command or law of nature consists primarily in the alienation of
oneself from one's nature, or the failure to be in actuality what
one is fundamentally and potentially, which for Cicero is the harshest
of penalties. This penalty, although it appears light as a result of its
remoteness from tangible experiences of physical or material harm, is
necessarily more painful than these since the most fundamental desire of
any natural being consists in the preservation of its nature. In this
manner the command of human nature also includes the reward of virtue,
that is, the eminently desirable fulfillment and completion of nature.
Further, this potential conflict and implicit command are both present
in the individual human being, who knows upon reflection that the
fulfillment of his nature requires acting at the behest of reason. Thus
the natural law derives its existence as law from the interrelated facts
of human nature. It exists as a general command which may be either
followed or rejected; it includes intrinsic rewards and penalties
attaching to compliance or deviation; (75) and it is universally
promulgated to knowing subjects.
In the second way, the natural law exists by way of its
instantiation in the particular commands for action which are issued by
the reason of the individual in response to particular circumstances. It
is in this second way that "Law ... is the mind and reason of the
prudent man, the standard by which Justice and Injustice are
measured." (76) Whereas the subject of the natural law in the first
way is the whole human being, in the second way its subject is the
sensual appetite. Since the nature of reason, including its proper
inclinations, entails directing the actions of the whole human being, it
must issue particular commands to the lower appetite and enlist its
support. This appetite, however, is wont to oppose reason's
commands and is capable of determining human actions in spite of them.
This power of opposition and resistance, as in its first and more
general manifestation, eliminates the possibility of a kind of despotic
determination and necessitates a rule by law. (77) Therefore in this
second way the individual, by following the injunctions of the most
general manifestation of natural law, issues commands to his appetite
which possess the character of the natural law in the manner of
particular participation or instantiation.
Absent this explicit derivation of the natural law, Cicero's
account of human nature is, moreover, remarkably consonant with that
provided by Aristotle. In the Physics, Aristotle defines
"nature" in general both in contradistinction to luck and
chance as what is "always or for the most part," (78) and as
inhering in beings as the source or cause of their movement and rest.
(79) The latter aspect, which constitutes the essential definition of
"nature," is identified with a thing's matter in the
sense of potency or necessary substratum for motion or change, and is
identified with the form (that is, the soul) in the sense of actuality
or fulfillment of this motion. (80) Applying this discussion of nature
in general to human beings in the Ethics, Aristotle begins, as does
Cicero, by placing human nature within a hierarchy of other natures.
(81) Giving human nature the same proper (formal) element identified by
Cicero, that of reason, Aristotle goes on to derive the notions of human
happiness and virtue. In the course of this derivation, Aristotle
encounters the same conflicting elements of human nature which are noted
by Cicero. Aristotle divides the human soul (which is human nature in
the sense of form) into rational and irrational elements, with the
irrational element being "naturally opposed to the rational
principle" (82) and apt to "fight against and resist that (the
rational) principle." (83) Thus Aristotle already possesses the
complex and dynamic account of hierarchically ordered and potentially
opposed natural inclinations which is taken up by Cicero.
A doctrine of natural law is, in fact, adumbrated by
Aristotle's brief mention of "unrestrained people" in
this context as well as in his further discussion of restraint and
unrestraint in Book 7. (84) In this latter discussion, Aristotle
describes "unrestraint" with reference to "the facts of
human nature." (85) These facts indicate the simultaneous presence
within the individual of a "universal opinion" which either
commands or forbids according to reason, and an "appetite"
which resists this command. (86) In this way "a man behaves
unrestrainedly under the influence (in a sense) of a rule and an
opinion, and of one not contrary in itself.., to the right rule."
(87) For this reason, Aristotle also states that the "lower animals
are not unrestrained" precisely because "they have no
universal judgment," which pertains only to reason. (88)
Aristotle's recognition and complex discussion of the
phenomena of restraint and unrestraint adds an important dimension to
his moral philosophy which is often overlooked by scholars who attempt
to dissociate Aristotelian "natural right" from theories of
natural law. It is within this discussion that Aristotle presents an
analysis of human action in general as the product of or conclusion from
universal premises and a particular premise. The universal premises
consist in propositions expressing some practical truth, such as
"dry food is good for every man" or "such and such food
is dry." (89) These universal premises join to form general
commands or prohibitions formulated by reason and addressed to the human
being as an agent concerned with particular actions. In Aristotle's
example, there may be a "universal opinion.., present in us"
not only indicating that we should refrain from performing some action,
but actually "forbidding" us to perform the action. (90) Since
Aristotle does not indicate that his analysis of human agency in this
place applies only to restrained or unrestrained persons, one may assume
that the person of "practical wisdom" discussed in the book
immediately preceding similarly possesses universal premises for action
that have this commanding/forbidding character. The prudent man, then,
is distinguished from the restrained man only in this: since his
appetites or passions have been properly habituated, they do not give
rise to competing premises which impede the efficacy of the "right
rule."
In this analysis of human action, and that of the human soul on
which it is based, Aristotle's thought seems to approach a concept
of natural law. Although Aristotle did not arrive at this concept
himself, Cicero shows in his writings that the notion of law is indeed
implicit in an Aristotelian account of human nature. (91) In this way,
then, Cicero lays the foundation for natural law theory on the soil of
Aristotle's nature.
II
Armed with an understanding of the Ciceronian-Aristotelian
conception of natural law, it is now (and only now) possible to provide
an adequate interpretation of the culminating statement of
"traditional" (for lack of a better term) natural law in the
writings of St. Thomas. In his Summa Theologica, St. Thomas, like
Cicero, attempts to derive the natural law from a rational encounter
with objective reality and an Aristotelian account of the nature of
human beings.
St. Thomas's so-called "Treatise on Law," (92) is,
of course, not a proper treatise at all but rather a relatively small
group of questions which occur in the middle of a much larger
enterprise. The subject of the Summa is the science of "sacred
doctrine," whose "chief aim.., is to teach the knowledge of
God." (93) St. Thomas gives a broad outline of this carefully
structured work in Question 2 of the First Part, indicating that he will
treat of "God," of "the rational creature's movement
towards God," and of "Christ, Who as man, is our way to
God." Under the second topic of inquiry St. Thomas considers both
"the last end of human life" and "those things by means
of which man may advance towards the end, or stray from it." (94)
The latter subject concerns "human acts," the treatment of
which is first divided into "universal" and
"particular" considerations. (95) Under the
"universal" heading, St. Thomas plans to treat of "human
acts themselves" and "their principles." (96) The
discussion of the principles of human acts begins in Question 49 of the
Prima Secundae, where this subject is once again divided into
"intrinsic" and "extrinsic" principles. (97) We
finally arrive at the questions regarding law in the treatment of the
"extrinsic" principles of human acts, which are identified as
the "devil" and "God." (98) The devil inclines human
actions to evil through "temptations," while God inclines
human actions to good through "Law" and "Grace."
(99)
In surveying the overall structure and orientation of the Summa, as
well as the context of the natural law discussion within the category of
"extrinsic" principles of human acts, it is easy to deny the
purely natural character of St. Thomas's natural law. Such a denial
is parallel to the claim that by making philosophy the
"handmaiden" (100) of sacred doctrine or theology, St. Thomas
does violence to the proper sphere of the former in the interests of
propounding the latter. (101) The notion that St. Thomas's method
is not truly philosophical and that his natural law smacks more of a
divine or eternal law has long enjoyed widespread currency. (102) It is
not surprising, then, that St. Thomas's natural law doctrine is a
particular focus of those who attempt to refute natural law theory in
general by arguing that it requires faith in a legislating God (and is
ipso facto not merely natural). The special aim of this discussion,
therefore, will consist in tracing St. Thomas's derivation of the
natural law with a watchful eye to the potential encroachment of either
divine or eternal law.
It is first important to note that the questions on law are
preceded not only by a treatment of God but also a thorough inquiry into
the nature of human beings. This inquiry is of crucial importance for
understanding the manner in which St. Thomas's natural law is
"natural." Although many contemporary interpretations of St.
Thomas's natural law rightly emphasize the importance of the
article concerning "Whether the Natural Law Contains Several
Precepts, or One Only," (103) a disproportionate focus on this
article often leads to an understanding of "nature" or the
"natural" which distorts St. Thomas's conception of these
terms in the case of human beings.
It is in this article that St. Thomas advances his well-known
theory of the "natural inclinations" which are "naturally
apprehended by reason as being good." If this article is read as
St. Thomas's single, definitive statement of the natural law, it
seems that natural means something like prereflective, instinctual, or
built-in. It seems, too, that by distinguishing the "practical
reason" from "speculative reason" (104) prior to the
discussion of inclinations within the article, St. Thomas means to
dissociate the former from the latter and exclude the role of
speculative reason or contemplative reflection in the workings of the
natural law. If this reading is correct, two conclusions relevant to our
purposes follow: (1) St. Thomas's natural law is not derived from
the philosophical understanding of human nature which precedes it in the
Summa; and (2) St. Thomas's natural law stands in contrast, rather
than continuity, with the Ciceronian-Aristotelian version which does
derive the principles of morality or natural law from a speculative or
reflective understanding of human nature. In order to combat these
conclusions and the reading on which they are based, it is necessary to
discuss St. Thomas's philosophical treatment of human nature in
some detail and determine the role that this treatment plays in his
understanding of the natural law.
Although the subject of the First Part of the Summa is
"God," St. Thomas includes in his consideration of God an
account of "the procession of creatures from Him." (105) This
procession occurs, moreover, in the threefold manner of
"production,.... distinction," and "government."
(106) Within the second heading, St. Thomas considers the distinction of
corporeal and spiritual creatures; after treating each of these, he
arrives at "the composite creature, corporeal and spiritual, which
is man." (107) St. Thomas divides his consideration of human beings
into a discussion of their "nature" and one of their
"origin." While the second discussion explicitly relates the
human creature to the transcendent God of theology, the discussion of
man's "nature" is wholly philosophical and devoid of any
theological premises. St. Thomas relies heavily in this section on
"the Philosopher," Aristotle, and his account of human nature
as derived from the Physics, De Anima, Posterior Analytics, and Ethics.
St. Thomas's discussion of human nature centers on a
consideration of its "powers," which provides the basis for
his later inquiry into the manner in which the rational creature
approaches God. The powers of which St. Thomas speaks are such not in
the sense of potestas (ability or might), but rather potentia
(potentiality) and virtus (virtue or excellence). (108) In these senses
the powers of the human soul are intrinsically ordered to operation as
potentiality is ordered to actuality. (109)
Approving the classification of "the Philosopher," St.
Thomas distinguishes five genera of powers in the human soul: the
vegetative, sensitive, appetitive, locomotive, and intellectual. (110)
In addition to their mere distinction, these kinds of powers exist in a
hierarchical order which corresponds with the order among the various
types of natural beings. (111) The vegetative, sensitive, and
intellectual powers in fact determine distinct types of "soul"
and "modes of living" which are proper to plants, animals, and
human beings respectively. (112) The order among these types of soul and
the corresponding modes of living arises out of the degree to which each
"surpasses the operation of the corporeal nature." (113)
In determining the level of superiority of a certain type of soul
to corporeal nature, St. Thomas employs Aristotle's definition of
nature as the principle of motion. The proper principle of the motion of
matter lies in its receptivity to an "extrinsic" impetus by
which it is moved. The proper principle of motion attaching to animate
beings (that is, beings with immaterial souls), on the other hand, lies
in an "intrinsic" principle by which it moves itself. (114)
Therefore, each type of soul exceeds materiality to the degree to which
it enables self-motion. Further, since the operation of self-motion
admits of degree according as it is accomplished independently of
determinate material instruments, a lesser dependence on materiality
corresponds to a greater degree of self-motion. The intellectual soul,
which distinguishes human beings from other animals and plants,
surpasses materiality to the greatest degree since it does not require
any material organ as its instrument. (115) Thus human beings, insofar
as they are human (that is, possess an intellectual soul), move
themselves by the intrinsic principle of intellectuality.
Despite the role of intellectuality (116) in distinguishing and
elevating human nature with respect to other natures, it is important to
keep in mind the fact that it remains but one kind of power among five
existing in a soul which is the substantial form of a body. (117) The
most important consequence of the latter aspect is that all intellectual
knowledge acquired by human beings occurs per viam sensus, "by way
of the senses." (118) Since it is invariably necessary that human
knowledge arise in this way, (119) human beings are intellectually
inferior to the angels who do not require phantasms produced by the
senses. (120) The former aspect further underscores the composite
character of the human being by placing his intellectuality within the
context of his fundamentally "animal" nature. Although the
intellect raises human beings above all other animals, it does not do so
to the extent of abandoning the proper characteristics attaching to
lower animal natures. (121) The properly human element of man coexists
with the properly animal and vegetative elements. In light of these
considerations, St. Thomas states that "the human soul ... is on
the confines of spiritual and corporeal creatures, and therefore the
powers of both meet together in the soul." (122)
St. Thomas further distinguishes two "ends" proper to the
intellect which follow on its apprehension: the "consideration of
truth" and the direction to operation. (123) This difference in the
application of the intellectual power results in the distinction between
the "speculative" and the "practical" intellects.
(124) Since these two intellects are really only accidental differences
within the intellectual power itself, there is a close correspondence
between the respective habits by which they are disposed to act. Both
the speculative and the practical intellects must begin with
indemonstrable first principles which are knowable immediately upon an
intellectual encounter with being; these first principles are held by
the habits of "understanding" (125) and
"synderesis," (126) respectively. From these starting-points
both manifestations of intellect proceed by combination to produce
conclusions, which are held by the habits of "science" (127)
and "prudence." (l28)
Despite the close analogy between the two manifestations of
intellect, an important difference arises in connection with their
relation to virtue. Virtues, defined in Aristotelian fashion as habits
which dispose to the good, are divided by St. Thomas into two types:
those which confer "aptness in doing good" and those which, in
addition, confer "the good use" of this aptness. (129) The
virtues of the speculative intellect belong to the former category,
while those of the practical intellect belong to the latter. The
disjunction between habit and act, to which this distinction in virtue
answers, has its source in the indeterminacy of the appetite. The
virtues of the practical intellect lead directly to good actions
precisely because they "presuppose the rectitude of the
appetite." (130) The indeterminacy of the appetite thus
necessitates the cultivation of virtues by which its
"rectitude" is secured.
In his Prologue to the Second Part of the Summa, St. Thomas
explains that after treating primarily of God in the First Part,
"it remains for us to treat of His image, that is, man, according
as he too is the principle of his actions, as having free choice and
control of his actions." The power of "free choice,"
failing under the general appetitive power, arises from the fact that
"reason in contingent matters may follow opposite courses."
(131) That man "has control of his actions," that is, that
they are "voluntary," similarly results from the
"rational appetite" by which human beings are capable of
acting for an intellectually apprehended end. (132) In both discussions
of the way in which human beings contain the principles of their actions
within themselves, it is the indeterminacy of the practical reason (or
intellect) which plays the decisive role.
A further indeterminacy in human action arises when the intellect,
which is proper to human beings, confronts the other powers of the human
soul which are shared in common with the animals. Since the sensitive
power is also an apprehensive one (like the intellect), it gives rise to
its own appetite whose object may contradict that proposed by the
intellectual appetite. (133) Thus, in defending the distinction between
moral and intellectual virtue from the Socratic position, (134) St.
Thomas states that "the appetitive part obeys the reason, not
blindly, but with a certain power of opposition." (135) It is for
this reason that the "rectitude of the appetite" includes both
the intellectual appetite and the sensual appetite; the former is
perfected by justice and prudence, (136) while the latter is perfected
by temperance and fortitude. (137)
In transitioning from his discussion of the virtues and vices to
his consideration of law, St. Thomas appears to transition from internal
principles of human action to external ones. This is, however, only
partly true. The distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic principles
in the realm of human action is not as clear as it appears at first
glance, as St. Thomas himself indicates at the outset of his discussion
of the subject. In treating the question of "whether there is
anything voluntary in human acts," St. Thomas states that
it is not contrary to the nature of the voluntary act that this
intrinsic principle be caused or moved by an extrinsic principle,
because it is not essential to the voluntary act that its intrinsic
principle be a first principle. (138)
In other words, there is a sense in which even human beings and
their actions are wholly dependent on an extrinsic principle insofar as
they are dependent on the first cause of all being, that is, God. In the
beginning of his discussion of law, (139) moreover, St. Thomas does not
list "law" as one of the extrinsic principles with which he is
concerned. The only extrinsic principles indicated are "the
devil" and "God." Each of these extrinsic principles
operates through certain instrumental causes; the devil through
"temptations," and God through "law" and
"grace." Grace, however, is earlier described as a
"habit," that is, an internal principle of human action, which
resides in the soul's essence. (140) It simply does not follow that
because God is an extrinsic principle of human actions he may only act
by means of purely extrinsic instrumental causes. There is nothing,
therefore, in the structure of the Summa itself which indicates a priori
whether St. Thomas's notion of law will prove to be wholly
extrinsic, primarily intrinsic, or some combination of both.
This is not, however, meant to imply that the location of the
natural law discussion within the framework of extrinsic principles is
merely by accident or coincidence. St. Thomas enters his consideration
of the natural law armed with philosophical proofs for the existence of
a transcendent God who governs the entirety of His creation. This
renders possible a derivation of the natural law within the context of
its relation to the eternal law of God. That which is present in
Cicero's derivation of the natural law in a relatively superficial
and conjectural manner is thus present in a fundamental and certain
manner for St. Thomas. Since St. Thomas is certain of the
"coherence of the whole" (141) both by the light of faith and
the testimony of reason, he views the natural law in the same manner in
which he views creation as a whole, namely, "in the light of
eternity." (142)
It is therefore consistent with St. Thomas's general
perspective to define the natural law as the "participation of the
eternal law in the rational creature." (143) This inclusion of the
"eternal law" in the very definition of the natural law leads
many commentators to dismiss the true "naturalness" of the
latter. Upon closer examination, however, the "rational
creature's participation" described by St. Thomas is in fact
quite different from the divine coercion with which it is often equated.
Although St. Thomas defines law in general as something
"pertaining to reason," (144) he distinguishes two ways in
which this relation to reason may occur: first, "as in one that
rules" and second, "by participation, as in one that is
ruled." (145) The eternal law clearly pertains to reason in the
first sense since it is "the very Idea of the government of things
in God." (146) As the eternal law applies to creatures that do not
possess intellect or reason, it has the character of law simply by
virtue of the Divine Reason as an external principle. If the lawfulness
of the natural law were similarly derived only from the Divine Reason
associated with the eternal law, St. Thomas's treatment of it as a
kind of law distinct from the eternal law would be largely inexplicable.
From the definition of the natural law, however, it is clear that it
attains recognition as a law by pertaining to reason in the second
sense, that is, "by participation." (147) For the rational
creature, that part of the eternal law which applies to him externally
is internalized by the power of the intellect apprehending the order
established within human nature by the Eternal Reason. This order is
manifested in the "order of natural inclinations" within human
beings, the discussion of which closely parallels Cicero's
regarding the "instincts" pertaining to the various levels of
natural being. (148) Thus the natural law is that by which "we
discern what is good and what is evil" (149) rather than simply
that by which our true good and perfection is externally prescribed.
This argument may also be illustrated by an analogy in the realm of
the speculative reason. Suppose someone were to draw a right triangle on
a sheet of paper and post this sheet on a bulletin board for all to see
(or perhaps on the Google homepage). After seeing this triangle a number
of times and forming an image of it in their minds, everyone would know
its basic characteristics, namely, that the hypotenuse is greater than
either of the other the two sides, that the right angle is wider than
either of the other two, and so on. The keenest minds would go much
farther than this, deducing that the right angle is equal to the sum of
the other two angles, the square on the hypotenuse is equal to the sum
of the squares on the other two sides, and so on. This entire body of
knowledge, however, is derived from and implicit in the manner in which
the triangle was originally drawn. In fact, the one who drew the
triangle happened to be Euclid, who did so with a knowledge not only of
its most complex attributes, but also of those of many other types of
figures which may be drawn. Since the knowledge which now exists in the
observers of the triangle preexisted in Euclid and was, in part,
extrinsically caused by his action of drawing it, ought we to deny these
observers the internal possession of this knowledge? Did Euclid infuse
the theorems relating to the triangle in its observers by the mere fact
of drawing it in this manner? Is it not more reasonable to concede that,
while Euclid's action was an extrinsic principle of the
observers' knowledge, this knowledge is now the shared possession
of both Euclid and those who rationally encountered his triangle?
In addition to establishing the "lawful" character of the
natural law, this discussion also illuminates the manner in which St.
Thomas's natural law is truly "natural," that is, not
dependent in the order of knowledge (150) on the eternal law or the
Divine Reason from which the eternal law emanates. Since the eternal law
is reflected in the objective order within and among created beings,
including the human being, all that is required for understanding the
first principles of the natural law is the intellectual procedure of
induction from objective reality. (151) Since, moreover, this derivation
proceeds from induction rather than demonstration, these principles are
indeed per se nota and indemonstrabilia, although not in the manner in
which these terms are understood by many new natural law theorists.
(152)
For St. Thomas, "every knowledge of truth is a kind of
reflection and participation of the eternal law," (153) and so
falls within the definition of the natural law insofar as this truth
directs the human being to the good of its nature. The most basic truths
which are relevant for human action, such as the superiority of the
intellect to the sensitive powers (corresponding to the superiority of
human beings to the other animals), are apprehended by the induction of
the intellect and held habitually by synderesis. Thus the fundamental
precept of the natural law consists for Aquinas in the general command
that "good is to be pursued and done, and evil is to be
avoided." (154) St. Thomas explicates the meaning of this first
precept by stating that "whatever the practical reason naturally
apprehends as man's good belongs to the precepts of the natural
law." (155) The "good," then, consists first and foremost
in the general state of living according to one's human nature
(that is, acting at the promptings of intellectual apprehension). In
this way, St. Thomas's natural law also possesses the twofold and
flexible character of Cicero's derivation; from the first and most
basic injunction to follow reason, the more particular applications of
reason also acquire the character of law by commanding the appetites of
individuals involved in concrete actions.
III
By locating St. Thomas's natural law doctrine within its
larger context in the Summa, that is, within a philosophy of human
nature, it becomes possible to discern both the Aristotelian roots of
this doctrine and the importance of Cicero as the crucial intermediary
between Aristotelian moral philosophy and Thomistic natural law. If
Cicero had not shown that an Aristotelian understanding of human nature
was compatible with, or even implied, a theory of natural law, St.
Thomas would likely have lacked the resources necessary to distinguish
the natural law as a kind of law distinct from both the eternal and
divine law. Thomistic natural law is, then, a developed statement of a
"traditional" natural law theory which counts Cicero, and
Aristotle through him, as its founding member.
It is important to note and briefly address two immediate
objections to this interpretation of Thomistic natural law theory before
concluding. The first contends that St. Augustine is a more obvious
candidate for influence on St. Thomas's natural law than Cicero.
(156) It is St. Augustine who "bookends" the question on the
natural law, appearing in the sed contra of the first and last articles
of Question 94; (157) Cicero, on the other hand, is not cited even once.
In answer to this objection, it must first be noted that the
primary function of the sed contra in St. Thomas's method is to
oppose the force of the objections with an authority sufficient to cast
doubt on their cogency. While the statements of the authority usually
support St. Thomas's own answer, this answer is often placed on an
entirely different foundation; for example, St. Thomas often cites
Scripture in his sed contra before providing a purely philosophical
answer to the question at hand. The strongest influences on St.
Thomas's own thought may be expected to appear in his respondeo
rather than in his sed contra. Since, moreover, it is within his own
answer that St. Thomas sets forth what he perceives to be the truth of
the matter, specific reference to his sources becomes less necessary.
Although St. Thomas does, of course, frequently provide such references
in his answers, insofar as he is setting forth the truth of the matter
the absence of a specific reference does not argue for the absence of
any precedent for his assertions. (158) The reason for this is that the
truth, in contrast to authoritative statements considered in themselves,
is a common rather than a particular good. Opinions and arguments,
therefore, lose their exclusive attachment to particular human beings
insofar as they approach closer to the actual truth. Thus, while
specific references provide clear evidence of some degree of influence,
a similarity of ideas and arguments without specific reference may in
fact indicate an even closer affinity to preceding thought for St.
Thomas.
Further, Cicero is cited by St. Thomas both within the
"Treatise on Law" (159) and, with some frequency, throughout
the Prima Secundae. (160) It is clear from these citations that St.
Thomas was familiar with Cicero's De Inventione, Tusculan
Disputations, and De Officiis, (161) and that he regarded Cicero as a
respected authority in moral and political philosophy. Question 94,
then, may only be persuasively insulated from Cicero's influence
with an argument from specific reference (or lack thereof) insofar as
this question itself may be understood in isolation from the remainder
of the questions on law and the Summa as a whole.
A second objection presses the point, briefly noted above, that
this account of natural law theory remains vulnerable to the
"naturalistic fallacy," or the derivation of values from
facts. (162) For this reason the account given may be of interest to the
historian of ideas, but cannot serve to reopen the philosophical
question of the existence of a natural law in the strict sense. While a
sufficient answer to this objection would necessarily extend far beyond
what may be attempted here, it may be possible to sketch the outlines
and direction of such an answer by briefly noting a few points of
relevance.
The logical impossibility of inferring or deriving values from
facts is generally traced to Hume's famous statement of the
"is-ought" problem. (163) This problem, both in its original
context within Hume's thought and in its various more recent
manifestations, follows from a specific limitation of the powers of
reason. Although reason is capable of complex deductions and abstruse
philosophizing, it is incapable of performing Aristotelian induction, or
the more primitive function of abstracting ideas which are at once
general and true from particular sense experiences. Thus reason stands
at a considerable remove from the realm of concrete reality within which
particular human actions occur, and by this distance is rendered
incompetent to perform its traditional function of directing toward
virtue or restraining from vice. The is--ought disjunction, then, is
intimately connected with Hume's thoroughgoing skepticism.
Although the new natural law theorists tend to deny such a
connection, simultaneously affirming the validity of Hume's
is-ought distinction and the ability of practical reason to grasp
objective moral truth, this denial rests on a dubiously rigid
distinction between the practical and speculative activities of reason.
The strictness of this distinction both lacks a persuasive basis in the
writings of St. Thomas and renders the meaning of
"intelligence" or reason problematically indeterminate. It
appears difficult, then, to accept the impossibility of the fact-value
inference without placing a radically skeptical epistemology at its
basis.
Thus, while St. Thomas's Summa Theologica remains the locus
classicus for natural law theory, this theory acquires more force and
persuasiveness when it is placed at the summit of a preceding tradition
of thought than when it is relegated to the foothills of an emerging
one. It seems that the modern transition from the traditional natural
law to the new natural law may indeed have been premature; and if this
is the case, what is required of current natural law theory is not the
abandonment of the more traditional version but rather its further
development and application to the pressing problems of contemporary
society.
University of Notre Dame
(1) John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1980).
(2) See Christopher Wolfe, Natural Law Liberalism (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2006).
(3) John Finnis and Germain Grisez, "The Basic Principles of
Natural Law: A Reply to Ralph McInerny," American Journal of
Jurisprudence 26 (1981): 31.
(4) See Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1953), 146-64; Frederick Crosson, "Religion and
Natural Law," American Journal of Jurisprudence 33 (1988): 1-3;
Ernest L. Fortin, "Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, and the Problem of
Natural Law," Mediaevalia 4 (1978): 179-82; Wolfe, Natural Law
Liberalism, 154-5; Michael Zuckert, "The Fullness of Being: Thomas
Aquinas and the Modern Critique of Natural Law," The Review of
Politics 69 (2007): 42. For interpretations of Aristotle that see the
natural law as latent, though not yet present, in Aristotle's
works, see Paul E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (New York:
University Press of America, 1971), 1-12 and Ronald P. McArthur,
"The Natural Law: A Perennial Problem," American Journal o f
Jurisprudence 26 (1981): 16.
(5) For the clearest expression of this interpretation, see Lloyd
L. Weinreb, Natural Law and Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1987), 39-40; also see Strauss, Natural Right, 154;
Sigmund, Natural Law, 20-5; James E. Holton, "Marcus Tullius
Cicero," in History of Political Philosophy, 3rd ed., ed. Leo
Strauss and Joseph Cropsey (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987),
155-75; Richard A. Horsley, "The Law of Nature in Philo and
Cicero," The Harvard Theological Review 71 (April 1978): 35-59;
Wolfe, Natural Law Liberalism, 156-7.
(6) St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the
English Dominican Province (New York: Benziger Bros., 1948), I-II, q.
94, a. 2; hereafter ST.
(7) Strauss, Natural Right, 163.
(8) Finnis, Natural Law, 49.
(9) Ibid., 280.
(10) These first two questions I take to be the basic concerns of
the new natural law theory.
(11) This question is treated by Wolfe in Natural Law Liberalism.
(12) See Fortin's description of the natural law as a
"misnomer of sorts, introduced into the tradition in somewhat
accidental fashion"; Ernest L. Fortin, "The New Rights Theory
and the Natural Law." Review of Politics 44 (Oct. 1982): 610.
(13) See Walter Nicgorski, "Cicero and the Rebirth of
Political Philosophy," The Political Science Reviewer 8 (Fall
1978): 63-102.
(14) Horsley, "The Law of Nature," 36.
(15) Ibid., 58.
(16) Marcus Tullius Cicero, De Legibus, trans. C. W. Keyes
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970), bk. 1, [section] 15,
p. 313.
(17) Ibid., 1.36, p. 337.
(18) That Cicero is referring especially to the Stoics is indicated
by the passages immediately following this statement, although in these
passages Cicero also asserts that the Old Academy, the Peripatetics, and
the Stoics are all in essential agreement. Zeno simply "changed the
terminology without altering the ideas" of the former two schools
(1.38, p. 339). It appears, then, that Cicero is not following any
particular school in the substance of his exposition (since they all
agree on this point), but is following the Stoics manner of expressing
it.
(19) Ibid., 1.36, p. 337.
(20) Ibid.
(21) Marcus Tullius Cicero, De Officiis, trans. Walter Miller
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2001), bk. 1, [section] 6,
p. 9 (my emphasis).
(22) See the interpretations of Strauss, Natural Right, 154;
Horsley, "The Law of Nature"; Nicgorski, "Cicero's
Paradoxes and His Idea of Utility," Political Theory 12 (Nov.,
1984): 557-78; Holton, "Marcus Tullius Cicero"; Crosson,
"Religion and Natural Law"; and Hadley Arkes, "That
'Nature Herself Has Placed in Our Ears a Power of Judging:'
Some Reflections on the 'Naturalism' of Cicero," in
Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, ed. Robert P. George (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1992), 245-77.
(23) Horsley, "The Law of Nature," 59.
(24) See Strauss, Natural Right; Fortin, "The New Rights
Theory"; and Crosson, "Religion and Natural Law." A
transcendent God may of course be the ultimate or ontologically primary
source of the natural law, but the very notion of a natural law in a
strict sense maintains a distinction between this law and either a
"Divine Law" or an "eternal law" which is either
directly promulgated by or immediately resides in God. St. Thomas
maintains this distinction in the questions on law in the Summa
Theologica.
(25) Horsley, "The Law of Nature," 58.
(26) This distinction is borrowed from Crosson's analysis in
"Religion and Natural Law."
(27) See Strauss, Natural Right, 154; Holton, "Marcus Tullius
Cicero"; see also Arkes, "Some Reflections," 274.
(28) This second form of critique of the notion of a natural law as
overly rigid or "categorical" will not be addressed directly
in what follows, although an answer to it is intimated by St.
Thomas's simultaneous assertion of the immutability (in one sense)
and flexibility (in another sense) of the natural law. Both
characteristics of the natural law also appear in Cicero's
writings, and in Aristotle's paradoxical statements regarding
natural justice in the Nicomachean Ethics, 5.7.1134b20-1135a5.
(29) Marcus Tullius Cicero, De Re Publica, trans. C. W. Keyes
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970), bk. 3 [section] 33,
p. 211.
(30) Ibid., 3.42, p. 217.
(31) Marcus Tullius Cicero, De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum, trans.
H. Rackham. Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 2006), bk. 2, [section] 59, p. 149.
(32) See especially 1.35, pp. 335-7.
(33) See De Legibus, 1.19, pp. 317-19, where Cicero asserts that
"Law ... is the mind and reason of the prudent man, the standard by
which Justice and Injustice are measured." In these passages Cicero
adds an element of flexibility to the rigidity of Laelius's
statements (without necessarily supplanting this element of rigidity).
(34) Cicero, De Officiis, 3.69, p. 339. De Legibus, 1.56, p. 361.
(35) De Legibus 1.14, p. 313; 1.17, p. 315.
(36) Ibid., 1.19, p. 319.
(37) De Officiis 3.69, pp. 339-41.
(38) De Legibus 1.18, p. 317.
(39) Ibid., 1.19, p. 317.
(40) Ibid., 1.23, pp. 321-3.
(41) Ibid.
(42) Ibid., 1.19, p. 319.
(43) Ibid., 1.17, p. 315.
(44) Ibid., 1.17-18, pp. 315-17.
(45) Crosson, "Religion and Natural Law," 6. See also
Holton, "Cicero," 170-72.
(46) For Cicero, indeed, the fact that a certain doctrine is
politically expedient is actually evidence for its theoretical truth.
See Cicero's attempted reconciliation of the expedient and the
morally right in Book 3 of De Officiis.
(47) Holton, "Cicero," 171.
(48) De Legibus 1.14, p. 313.
(49) De Legibus, 1.16, p. 315.
(50) Ibid.
(51) Ibid., 1.17, p. 317.
(52) Ibid., 1.24, p. 323.
(53) This "inessential role" for the transcendent God
ought to be understood in an epistemological rather than an ontological
sense.
(54) Ibid., 1.21, pp. 319-21.
(55) Ibid.
(56) In support of this point see also Cicero's reference to
the function of "Nature, alone and unaided" in 1.27, p. 327.
(57) De Officiis 1.11, p. 13.
(58) Ibid.
(59) De Legibus, 1.30, p. 329.
(60) Ibid.
(61) Ibid.
(62) De Officiis, 1.11, p. 13.
(63) Ibid.
(64) Ibid., 1.12, p. 15.
(65) Ibid.
(66) De Legibus, 1.31, p. 331.
(67) Ibid.
(68) De Officiis 1.105, p. 107.
(69) On this point of Cicero's account of human inclinations,
see Nicgorski, "Cicero's Paradoxes," 564-6.
(70) De Officiis, 1.101, p. 103. I have altered the translation of
the first clause in order to include "nature," which is
present in the Latin.
(71) De Legibus, 1.18, p. 317.
(72) Finnis, Natural Law, 33; Robert P. George, "Natural Law
and Human Nature," in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, 32.
(73) See Cicero's derivation of "law" from the idea
of "choosing" as one of the elements of its proper notion in
De Legibus 1.19, p. 317.
(74) In this way, one may, as Cicero does, establish the existence
of a law or command from the existence of its proper effects (effects
that could follow only from law or command). This is a kind of
effect-to-cause (quia) argument which Fortin, for example, does not
allow for in his discussion of the lawfulness of the natural law in
"The New Rights Theory."
(75) The distinction between "intrinsic" and
"externally imposed" penalties and rewards is centrally
important to an understanding of the natural law. Although punishments
and rewards are indeed the proper effects of command and law, these need
not be imposed by some external "observer," as Crosson,
Fortin, and many others would have it. If a law commands some good,
disobedience of this law necessarily entails the deprivation of good.
This penalty is an internal consequence of the act of disobedience
itself, and not something appended to disobedience after the fact.
(76) Cicero, De Legibus, 1.19, pp. 317-19. I have replaced
"intelligent" in the translation with "prudent" to
render the Latin more accurately.
(77) For comparison see Aristotle's statement in the Politics
that "the intellect rules the appetites with a constitutional and
royal rule," in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon
(New York: Random House, 1941), 1.5.1254b4.
(78) Aristotle, Physics, in The Basic Works of Aristotle,
2.4.195b30 9.200b10.
(79) Ibid., 2.1.192b22.
(80) Ibid., 2.1.193a1-193b22.
(81) Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, in The Basic Works of
Aristotle, 1.7.1097b25-1098a5.
(82) While Aristotle and Cicero would say "naturally
opposed," St. Thomas would describe this frequent opposition as an
effect of the Fall, and therefore the opposition would be
"natural" in the sense of fallen nature, but not natural in
the sense of original nature.
(83) Aristotle, Ethics, 1.13.1102b13-30.
(84) Ibid., 1102b21.
(85) Ibid., 7. 3.1147a 25.
(86) Ibid., 1147a30-5.
(87) Ibid., 1147a35-1147b2.
(88) Ibid., 1147b4-6.
(89) Ibid., 1147a5-7.
(90) Ibid., 1147a32. Although Aristotle's term here (koluousa)
may be translated less strongly as "checking" or
"preventing," it is most often, and not by an unwarranted
license, translated as "forbidding."
(91) The question of whether Cicero read Aristotle's works
himself, or was merely familiar with the thought of his followers in the
Peripatetic school, is not of crucial importance to this particular
argument (assuming a sufficient amount of continuity between the two
sources). However, it seems that Cicero did read Aristotle's works
himself from De Finibus 3.10, p. 227.
(92) St. Thomas, ST, I-II, qq. 90-108.
(93) Ibid., I-II, prooemium.
(94) Ibid., I-II, q. 1, prooemium.
(95) Ibid., q. 6, prooemium.
(96) Ibid.
(97) Ibid., q. 49, prooemium.
(98) Ibid., q. 90, prooemium.
(99) Ibid.
(100) Ibid., I, q. l, a. 5, ad. 2.
(101) See Fortin's translation of ancilla as "slave"
in "St. Thomas Aquinas," in History of Political Philosophy,
271. While "slave" is a possible translation of ancilla, the
connotations of this translation run counter to the spirit of St.
Thomas's use of philosophy throughout the ST.
(102) See, for example, Fortin, "St. Thomas Aquinas," as
well as "Thomas Aquinas as a Political Thinker," Perspectives
on Political Science 26 (Spring, 1997): 92-7; see also Crosson,
"Religion and Natural Law," 8-13.
(103) ST, I-II, q. 94, a. 2.
(104) Although the extent to which St. Thomas means to distinguish
the two applications of reason even in this article is open to question,
since the distinction occurs within a discussion of the similar or
analogous character of the two types of reasoning.
(105) St. Thomas, ST, I, q. 2, prooemium.
(106) Ibid., q. 44, prooemium.
(107) Ibid., also q. 75, prooemium.
(108) See ST, I, q. 75 and q. 77, prooemium.
(109) Ibid., q.77, a.3.
(110) Ibid., q. 78, a.1.
(111) Ibid.; see also I. q. 77, a. 4. Here we find a distinct point
of similarity with the accounts of Aristotle and Cicero.
(112) Ibid., q. 78, a.1; see also I, q. 18, a. 3.
(113) Ibid., q. 78, a. 1.
(114) Ibid.
(115) Ibid. While the intellectual soul does not require any
material organ as its instrument, this does not deny the necessity of
the material sense organs to the operation of the intellect since all
knowledge comes per viam sensus.
(116) St. Thomas's intellectus is a close equivalent to
Cicero's ratio and Aristotle's logos in relation to a
conception of human nature.
(117) St. Thomas, ST, I, q. 75, a. 5 and I, q. 76, a. 1.
(118) Ibid., q. 76, a. 5.
(119) At least while in the natural state. See Ibid., q. 89, aa.
1-2.
(120) Ibid., q. 85.1; also I, q. 79, a. 2.
(121) For an interesting comparison, see Cicero's criticism of
the Stoic position in book 4 of De Finibus.
(122) St. Thomas, ST, I, q. 77, a. 2.
(123) Ibid., q. 79, aa. 11-12.
(124) Ibid.
(125) Ibid., I-II, q. 57, a. 2.
(126) Ibid., I, q. 79, a. 12. St. Thomas's term
"synderesis" is normally left untranslated due to the lack of
a sufficiently precise English equivalent. Although it is commonly
understood in a loose manner as "conscience," it cannot be
translated as conscience since St. Thomas speaks of conscientia in the
next article. Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger (now Pope Benedict XVI)
interestingly proposed "translating" synderesis with the Greek
word anamnesis in his paper "Conscience and Truth" (presented
at the 10th Workshop for Bishops, February 1991, in Dallas, Texas. See
http://ewtn.com/library/CURIA/RATZCONS.HTM).
(127) St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q. 57, a. 2.
(128) Ibid., aa. 4-5.
(129) Ibid., a. 1.
(130) Ibid., a. 4.
(131) Ibid., I, q. 83, a. 1.
(132) Ibid., I-II, q. 6, a. 1.
(133) Ibid., I, q. 80, a. 1.
(134) At least as interpreted by Aristotle in the Ethics,
6.13.1144b19.
(135) St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q. 58, a. 2. Note that this is
essentially a paraphrase of Aristotle's description of this
situation in the Ethics.
(136) See Ibid., q. 61, a. 1.
(137) Ibid., a. 2.
(138) Ibid., q. 6, a. 1, ad. 1.
(139) Ibid., q. 90, prooemium.
(140) Ibid., q. 50, a. 2.
(141) James V. Schall, "The Uniqueness of the Political
Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas," Perspectives on Political Science 26
(Spring, 1997): 89.
(142) Fortin, "Thomas Aquinas as a Political Thinker,"
92.
(143) St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q. 91, a. 2.
(144) St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q. 90, a. 1.
(145) Ibid., a. 3, ad. 1.
(146) Ibid., q. 91, a. 1.
(147) See Ibid., a. 2, ad. 3.
(148) St. Thomas's discussion occurs in ST, I-II, q. 91, a. 2
and in I-II, q. 94, a. 2. Cicero's similar discussion occurs in the
De Officiis, beginning in 1.11, p. 13 (see my p. 503).
(149) St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q. 9, a. 2 (my emphasis).
(150) At this point the distinction Finnis draws between the
"epistemological" and "ontological" orders, which is
present both throughout the ST and in Aristotle's Physics, becomes
relevant.
(151) See St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q. 93, a. 2.
(152) The understanding of indemonstrable principles by the new
natural law theorists does not include any positive explanation, such as
that provided by the process of induction, but only the negative
assertion of indemonstrability.
(153) St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q. 93, a. 2.
(154) Ibid., q. 94, a. 2.
(155) Ibid.
(156) This objection is drawn from Fortin, "The Problem of
Natural Law," 191-9, and Mary Keys, Aquinas, Aristotle, and the
Promise of the Common Good (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2006), 102-10. Although Keys argues here for the "newness of
Aquinas's moral foundation" rather than the strength of St.
Augustine's influence, the form of argument utilized would favor
St. Augustine rather than Cicero as an influence on St. Thomas's
natural law doctrine.
(157) Noted in Keys, Promise of the Common Good, 108.
(158) See Keys's argument in Promise of the Common Good,
107-10.
(159) St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q. 91, a. 3; I-II, q. 95, a. 3, obj. 3;
I-II, q. 99, a. 5, ad. 1.
(160) For an index of these citations see St. Thomas Aquinas, Basic
Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas, ed. Anton C. Pegis (New York: Random
House, 1945), 1164.
(161) St. Thomas was, of course, also familiar with portions of
Cicero's other works through St. Augustine's writings.
(162) See Finnis, Natural Law, 33 and George, "Natural Law and
Human Nature," 32.
(163) David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Baltimore, Md:
Penguin Books, 1969), bk. 3, part 1, [section] 1.
Correspondence to: 217 O'Shaughnessy Hall, Department of
Political Science, Notre Dame, IN 46556.